On 3/25/25 I copied and pasted the
entire article from Encyclopedia Britannica onto an electronic page; I have
done some minor editing to hold the piece together, and will comment on it when
appropriate. The article is entitled: free will and moral responsibility—Encyclopedia
Britannica. Here is the article:
Britannica (B after this): “
free will
and moral responsibility
Article
History
Also called:
problem of moral responsibility
free
will and moral responsibility, the problem of reconciling
the belief
that people are morally responsible for what they do with the apparent fact
that humans do not have free will
because their actions are causally determined.
It is an ancient and enduring philosophical puzzle.”
My
response: We are overawed by the powerful, impressive and ever increasing
evidence from neuroscientists like Robert Sapolsky that free will is an illusion,
that as Robert suggests, we are controlled by nature and nurture and the
interactions between the two.
My
confident rejection of all of this very daunting, amassing evidence is that
yes, you scientists are factually proving that so many factors studied do
indicates that humans are externally controlled, but that that soley is amassing
empirical evidence on the physical part of our existence: the angelic or
spiritual side of our emerged consciousness, especially when it emerges as the
individuated self, is infinitely rich and immaterially sourced, so all their
fancy experiments, and sweeping claims, though interesting and rich, cannot
capture the incalculable richness, the infinite possibilities latent within the
consciousness of the simplest human soul out there.
We
are both-determined and self-determined at the same time and in the same
person, so the free consciousness of the creative individuator does field a
free will that is not absolutely, limitlessly free, but it is quite far
advanced along such lines. Physical facts, neuroscientfically gathered, do not apply
to the human soul. The physicalist is not able to detect let alone disprove the
metaphysical fact that one is free, a little as a nonindividuator, and almost
totally of free will, if she were an impressive individuators, an artistic
great soul long practicing her craft.
B: “Freedom
and responsibility
Historically,
most proposed solutions to the problem of free will and moral
responsibility have attempted to establish that humans do have free will.
But what does free will consist of? When people make decisions or perform
actions, they usually feel as though they are choosing or acting freely. A
person may decide, for example, to buy apples instead of oranges, to vacation
in France rather than in Italy, or to call a sister in Nebraska instead of a
brother in Florida. On the other hand, there are at least some situations in
which people seem not to act freely, as when they are physically coerced or
mentally or emotionally manipulated. One way to formalize the intuitive idea of
free action is to say that people act freely if it is true that they could have
acted otherwise. Buying apples is ordinarily a free action because in ordinary
circumstances one can buy oranges instead; nothing forces one to buy apples or
prevents one from buying oranges.
Yet
the decisions people make are the result of their desires, and their desires
are determined by their circumstances, past experiences, and psychological and
personality traits—their dispositions,
tastes, temperaments, levels of intelligence, and so on. Circumstances,
experiences, and traits in this sense are obviously the result of many factors
outside the individual’s control, including upbringing and perhaps even genetic
makeup. If this is correct, then one’s actions may ultimately be no more the
result of free will than one’s eye colour
is.”
My
response: Our natural and nurtured influences from inside and outside of us,
our unconscious, our desires, luck, indeterminism, causal determinism, chance, and
sheer randomness—they all influence us, but the self can and does still choose
freely alternative options based solely on changing one’s mind at this
particular moment, for sound reasons, for some whim, or by some instinct to
change.
B:
“The existence of free will seems to be presupposed by the notion of moral
responsibility. Most people would agree that one cannot be morally responsible
for actions that one could not help but perform. Moreover, moral praise and
blame, or reward and punishment,
seem to make sense only on the assumption that the agent in question is morally
responsible. These considerations
seem to imply a choice between two implausible alternatives: either (1) people
have free will, in which case their actions are not determined by their
circumstances, past experiences, and psychological and personality traits, or
(2) people do not have free will, in which case they are never morally
responsible for what they do. This dilemma is the problem of free will and
moral responsibility.”
My
response: I detect no dilemma: we have free will and accompanying moral
responsibility, though we can sympathize and empathize, and try to understand
and give the benefit of the doubt where possible. Extenuating circumstances do
apply, but that does not absolve almost any of us for some, most or near
complete blame for our sins and crimes committed.
B: “Determinism
Determinism
is the view that, given the state of the universe (the complete physical
properties of all its parts) at a certain time and the laws of
nature operative in the universe at that time, the state of the
universe at any subsequent time is completely determined. No subsequent state
of the universe can be other than what it is. Since human actions, at an appropriate
level of description, are part of the universe, it follows that humans cannot
act otherwise than they do; free will is impossible. (It is important to
distinguish determinism from mere causation.
Determinism is not the thesis that every event has a cause, since causes do not
always necessitate their effects. It is, rather, the thesis that every event is
causally inevitable. If an event has occurred, then it is impossible that it
could not have occurred, given the previous state of the universe and the laws
of nature.)
Philosophers
and scientists who believe that the universe is deterministic and that
determinism is incompatible with free will are called “hard” determinists.
Since moral responsibility seems to require free will, hard determinism implies
that people are not morally responsible for their actions. Although the
conclusion is strongly counterintuitive,
some hard determinists have insisted that the weight of philosophical argument
requires that it be accepted. There is no alternative
but to reform the intuitive beliefs in freedom and moral responsibility. Other
hard determinists, acknowledging that such reform is scarcely feasible,
hold that there may be social benefits to feeling and exhibiting moral
emotions, even though the emotions themselves are based on a fiction. Such
benefits are reason enough for holding fast to pre-philosophical beliefs about
the existence of both free will and moral responsibility, according to these
thinkers.”
My
response: There are of course social benefits to be maintained if we assume
people are free and morally responsible for their choices and actions, though
they are robots, but I fear that if we tell people they are robots, they, still
fielding free wills however undisciplined by self-restraint, will not develop
into morally and spiritually good persons, knowing God is keeping a list,
checking it twice to see who is naughty or nice.
To
teach the young that they are robots is to teach them a lie, and it is to set
loose these basically evil monsters upon society with no moral prohibition,
self-enforced, to curb their misbehavior. There is no quicker way to set up
hell on earth and treating people like robots or pieces of clay as Eric Hoffer
warned, is to set up authoritarian dispensations in every country, and that is
to increase needless suffering in the world.
B:
“The extreme alternative to determinism is indeterminism, the view that at
least some events have no deterministic cause but occur randomly, or by chance.
Indeterminism is supported to some extent by research in quantum
mechanics, which suggests that some events at
the quantum
level are in principle unpredictable (and therefore random).”
.
B: “Libertarianism
Philosophers
and scientists who believe that the universe is indeterministic and that humans
possess free will are known as “libertarians” (libertarianism in this sense is
not to be confused with the school of political
philosophy called libertarianism).
Although it is possible to hold that the universe is indeterministic and that
human actions are nevertheless determined, few contemporary philosophers defend
this view.
Libertarianism
is vulnerable
to what is called the “intelligibility” objection. This objection points out
that people can have no more control over a purely random action than they have
over an action that is deterministically inevitable; in neither case does free
will enter the picture. Hence, if human actions are indeterministic, free will
does not exist.”
My
response: One can take a peripatetic gendering through all the natural factors
(indeterminism, chance, quantum theory, chaos theory and luck), and these
generally could be considered as evidence in favor of human free will existing
and being operative in each agent, but, still this intelligibility objection
shared shows that even these “favorable”
conditions—perhaps necessary but not sufficient conditions for free will to
exist—are not enough to prove we have free will, but, ultimately, as a
epistemic moderate and as a metaphysical moderate, I deny that humans can prove
for sure that we have free will, or that determinism or randomness are our only
behavioral outcomes possible.
That
the majority of humans subjective feel that they are free, and that God exists,
and I propose that the near universality of these beliefs is empirical if
subjective evidence that God, free will, and the spiritual world are axiomatic
concepts to be accepted on faith at face value, and such a resolution will help
clear up this thorny issue of human free will.
How
do molecules and subatomic particles come together as primitive cells, lead to
the introduction of life in the world? It seems miraculous or magical to me
that life is sparked purely from an accidental or chance mixing of elementary
particles, but I cannot say for sure that it did not happen that way, or that
it did, or that God exists or does not exist.
I
view human consciousness as the ghost in the machine, and the skeptical neuroscientist
can pile up all the daunting, impressive, perhaps irrefutable evidence that we
have no free will, but these experiments, tests and observations with very
fancy technology does not study the nature of the individual soul, our divine
spark accompanied by God’s grace, and that is affiliated with though separated
from God’s consciousness, which is infinite,. Thus, I am neither rattled nor too
concerned scientific tests disproving free will, for our consciousnesses are
connected to infinite power and infinite spiritual power and life force, and
that cannot be pushed aside by materialistic, mechanistic, reductionist
experimenting, no matter how impressive and substantiated by other independent
tests.
B:
“The German Enlightenment philosopher Immanuel
Kant (1724–1804), one of the earliest defenders of
libertarianism, attempted to overcome the intelligibility objection, and
thereby to make room for moral responsibility, by proposing a kind of dualism
in human
nature. In his Critique
of Practical Reason (1788), Kant claimed that humans
are free when their actions are governed by reason.
Reason (what he sometimes called the “noumenal self”) is in some sense
independent of the rest of the agent, allowing the agent to choose morally.
Kant’s theory requires that reason be disconnected from the causal order in
such a way as to be capable of choosing or acting on its own and, at the same
time, that it be connected to the causal order in such a way as to be an integral
determinant of human actions. The details of Kant’s view have been the subject
of much debate, and it remains unclear whether it is coherent.”
My
response: As a staunch defender of Objectivist epistemology, I have some real
reservations about Kant generally, but I like what is said about his
dualism—interactionist dualism?—in human nature. We are, at the same time,
half-beast and half-angel, so we are biological, material animals, and
rational/angelic spirits in our consciousness, and that depiction of human
nature may not be pat, simple or even coherent, but it is the human reality, no
more, no less.
B:
“Although libertarianism was not popular among 19th-century philosophers, it
enjoyed a revival in the mid-20th century. The most influential of the new
libertarian accounts were the so-called “agent-causation” theories. First
proposed by the American philosopher Roderick
Chisholm (1916–99) in his seminal
paper “Human Freedom and the Self” (1964), these theories hold that free
actions are caused by agents themselves rather than by some prior event or
state of affairs. Although Chisholm’s theory preserves the intuition
that the ultimate origin of an action—and thus the ultimate moral
responsibility for it—lies with the agent, it does not explain the details or
mechanism of agent-causation. Agent-causation is a primitive, unanalyzable
notion; it cannot be reduced to anything more basic. Not surprisingly, many
philosophers found Chisholm’s theory unsatisfactory. What is wanted, they
objected, is a theory that explains what freedom is and how it is possible, not
one that simply posits freedom. Agent-causation theories, they maintained,
leave a blank space where an explanation ought to be.”
My
response: We cannot explain what freedom is or what it is to the satisfaction
of the mechanistic determinist because these ontological facts about human
nature are primary, and just are, so concepts and words cannot capture their
essence. If they are infinitely expansive in the properties they are comprised
of, and in how the soul-in-the-body interacts with others in the world is not
explanatory (at least for now) I think there is enough evidence provided by
Objectivists that we do wield free will as we focus our rational abilities to
make sense of the world.
B: “Compatibilism
Ancient and medieval compatibilism
Compatibilism,
as the name suggests, is the view that the existence of free will
and moral
responsibility is compatible with the truth of determinism.
In most cases, compatibilists (also called “soft” determinists) attempt to
achieve this reconciliation by subtly revising or weakening the commonsense
notion of free will.”
Objectivists
from The Atlas Society by 2010 had firmly refuted compatibilism, because it
disallows robust, libertarian properties to a free will, accepted and
experienced by each agent, in her personal life, and billions of people
subjectively experiencing this commonsense notion of free will as operating in
their minds is powerful reminded that reality is not what the neuroscientists
claim that it is counterfactually and counterintuitively.
I
know we are part determined and part-free naturally, but as we individuate, our
intelligence, language and concept-wielding grows and expands, and we can focus
our minds so we become more and more free willing, while the automatic and more
instinctually functioning systems in our bodies and minds still govern themselves
unconsciously by rules we may not understand or identity, but exist in and
operate beneficially inside us. This moderate compatibilism exists, I believe
as we go from being mostly caused by deterministic events, to increasingly and
then mostly are self-determining as the causal agent and originator of our
choices and actions as individuators.
The
Objectivist dislike more typical compatibilism as unnecessarily restrictive of
human enjoyment of their free willing possibilities and ends, and discount it
as true or realistic, as not being how humans think, choose or act.”
B:
“Compatibilism has an ancient history, and many philosophers have endorsed
it in one form or another. In Book III of the Nichomachean
Ethics, Aristotle
(384–322 bce) wrote that humans are responsible for the actions they freely
choose to do—i.e., for their voluntary actions. While acknowledging that “our dispositions
are not voluntary in the same sense that our actions are,” Aristotle believed
that humans have free will because they are free to choose their actions within
the confines of their natures. In other words, humans are free to choose
between the (limited) alternatives
presented to them by their dispositions. Moreover, humans also have the special
ability to mold their dispositions and to develop their moral characters. Thus,
humans have freedom in two senses: they can choose between the alternatives
that result from their dispositions, and they can change or develop the
dispositions that present them with these alternatives. One might object that
the capacity
for self-examination and reflection presupposed by this kind of freedom implies
the existence of something in humans that is outside the causal order. If this
is so, then Aristotle’s compatibilism is really a disguised form of libertarianism.”
My
response: This weird libertarian compatibilism that the writers at Britannica
are attributing to Aristotle seems attractive and plausible to me, and it might
be the kind of compatibilism that would appeal to a metaphysical libertarian
such as I am.
We
are born determined and enslaved by reality and our natures more than we are
born free and/or self-determining and free-willing, so the telos for human
maturation is to individuate and live as a free-willing maverick, as fully and
best as one can, so we can strengthen our shrunken free will to make it robust,
not unlike how a puny 20-year old can lift weights to become powerful and
bulked up. We were born other-caused, and as we maverize, increasingly are we
the originator and source of our will choices, so we grow in self-causation.
B: “For medieval
Scholastic
philosophers, free will was a theological
problem. If God is the prime mover—the first cause
of all things and events in the universe, including human actions—and if the
universe is deterministic, then it seems to follow that humans never act
freely. How can humans do other than what God has caused them to do? How then
can they be morally responsible for their actions? An analogous
problem obtains regarding God’s omniscience: if God, being omniscient, has
foreknowledge of every choice that humans make, how can humans choose other
than what God knows they will choose?”
My
response: God is square with us, and would not deceive us, lie to us, or
torture us. Based on these presuppositions, I must take it on faith that God
has foreknowledge and omniscience, but not where his smart beings are given the
gift of free will by De so that they are free and make moral choices, so they
are responsible for their actions. How this contradiction be justified, I know
not, but this is how the world sems to work.
It
could be that God made the world so that those with free will, that their part
of reality remains unknown to God who is otherwise omniscient, and that God
places this imposition upon Deself as a gift to humanity that they are free to
choose how to choose live and which way to turn, without divine foreknowledge
wiping out their free will or responsibility. To be free is a gift of love, and
God may play dice sometimes with the universe, but God is faithful and
trustworthy and allows people a zone of privacy wherein their choices are made
by people and not known in advance by anyone. I accept this on faith in God’s
kindness, square-dealing, and sense of fairness.
B:
“In
the late 4th and early 5th centuries, St.
Augustine played a key role in combining
Greek philosophy with Christianity;
his attempts to reconcile
human freedom with Christian notions such as divine foreknowledge are still
cited by theologians. According to Augustine, God—a perfect, omnipotent,
and omniscient being—exists outside the realm of time. Temporal directionality
does not exist for God, as it does for humans. Hence, it makes no sense to
attribute foreknowledge of human choices to God.:’’
My
response Perhaps St. Augustine was correct, that God’s foreknowledge does not
apply to the temporal human world.
B:
“Nearly a millennium later, St.
Thomas Aquinas (1225–74) grappled with the same
problems. Like Augustine, he lived during a major turning point in Western intellectual
history, when the relationship between philosophy
and religion
was being freshly examined and recast. In his Summa
theologiae (1265/66–73), Aquinas wrote that if
humans do not have free will, all “counsels, exhortations, commands,
prohibitions, rewards, and punishments would be in vain”; such a conclusion
is simply inconceivable. In response to the apparent conflict between freedom
and God’s role as the prime mover of human wills, Aquinas claimed that God is
in fact the source of human freedom. This is because God moves humans “in
accordance with our voluntary natures.” “
My
response: God is the source of human freedom because there can be no spiritual,
moral or ontological goodness without conscious entities possessing free will,
so they may extend God’s realm in the world, extending God’s rule as far as
possible, so humans therein possess freedom of will, freedom of action, freedom
of conscience, free speech and free thinking; these godly freedoms are not
absolute, but are close enough, for God does move us in accordance with our
human natures.
B:
“Just as by moving natural causes God does not prevent their acts being
natural, so by moving voluntary causes He does not deprive their actions of
being voluntary.
Because
humans are created by God, their wills are naturally in harmony with his. Thus,
God’s role as prime mover need not get in the way of free agency.”
My
response: I disagree with Aquinas when he states that because humans are
created by God, their wills are naturally in harmony with his. God created us
with natural depravity built into us, so there is no automatic, easy way for our
wills to be in harmony with God’s will. The harmony can be achieved but not
without persistent, tough human effort. That harmony is an achieved harmony
established between humans and Gld. This harmony is and unstable fragile and unstable
pact, rebuilt and honored daily.
B: “Modern compatibilism
Following
the rediscovery of Classical learning during the Renaissance,
philosophers sympathetic
to compatibilism shifted their focus from the divine back to the individual.
The English philosopher Thomas
Hobbes (1588–1679) argued that the only condition necessary for
free will and moral responsibility is that there be a connection between one’s
choices and one’s actions. In his Leviathan
(1651), he asserted that free will is “the liberty of the man [to do] what he
has the will, desire, or inclination to do.” If people are able to do the
things they choose, then they are free.”
My
response: Free will is freedom of mental choice, not ensuing freedom of action
to take action.
B:
“The Scottish
Enlightenment philosopher David Hume
(1711–76), another staunch compatibilist, maintained that the apparent
incompatibility between determinism and free will rests on a confusion about
the nature of causation.
Causation is a phenomenon that humans project onto the world, he believed. To
say that one thing (A) is the cause of another thing (B) is nothing more than
to say that things like A have been constantly conjoined with things like B in
experience and that an observation of a thing like A inevitably brings to mind
the idea or expectation of a thing like B. There is nothing in nature itself
that corresponds to the “necessary connection” thought to exist between two
things that are causally related. Since there is just this kind of regularity
between human choices on the one hand and human actions on the other, it
follows that human actions are caused by human choices, and this is all that is
needed for free will. As Hume claimed in his Enquiry
Concerning Human Understanding (1748), “By liberty we can only
mean a power of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the
will.” “
My
response: Causal relations may be a necessary connection between causal events
and object effected events, or but a weaker relationship.
B:
“The British philosopher John
Stuart Mill (1806–73) was the major champion of
compatibilism in the 19th century. He proposed that a person is free when “his
habits or his temptations are not his masters, but he theirs.” Unfree people,
in contrast, are those who obey their desires even when they have good reasons
not to. Mill’s position is situated at an interesting turning point in
compatibilist thinking. It echoes Kant in its reliance on reason as the vehicle
of freedom, but it also anticipates contemporary
compatibilism in its notion that a free person is one whose internal desires
are not at odds with reason.”
My
response: There is a free will to choose alternate choices and there is living
in a state of political, moral, or spiritual freedom, free from sin and
tyranny, tyranny imposed by oneself, externally by a political oligarchy, or if
the Devil is calling the shots for one.
One
has free will to decide if his desires, his habits,or his temptations rule his
choice selection, or if he rationally firmly decide how to choose or act in
line with his moral code, to preserve his honor, his state of virtue, his
reputation, his good will, his good character and his standing with the good
deity whom he worships.
My
recommendation that the wise and moral person would be more guided by her right
reason than her sentiments or moral sense, but she would listen to both sources
of suggestion before rationally, consciously making her choice between
alternative routes of action.
Her
internal desires or external pressure may or may not coincide with her
enlightened best interest, but she normally will listen or enforce only those
desires consistent with her moral standard. This she wields freely, this power
to choose among alternatives.
B:
“In his Ethical
Studies (1876), Mill’s countryman F.H. Bradley
(1846–1924) argued that neither compatibilism nor libertarianism comes close to
justifying what he called the “vulgar notion” of moral responsibility.
Determinism does not allow for free will because it implies that humans are
never the ultimate originators of their actions. Indeterminism does no better,
for it can imply only that human decisions are completely random. Yet it is
intuitively obvious, according to Bradley, that humans have free will, and no
philosophical argument in the world will convince anyone otherwise. He thus
advocated a return to common sense. Given that the philosophical theory of
determinism necessarily conflicts with people’s deep-rooted moral intuitions,
it is better to abandon the former rather than the latter.”
My
response: I would suppose that libertarianism would be the proper stance for
Bradley on free will, because we intuitively or subjectively know we are free
willing, and thus it is common sense that the strong but not absolute personal
capacity of free willing is the coin of the realm.
B: “Contemporary compatibilism . . .”
B:
“Notwithstanding Bradley’s argument, compatibilism remained popular among
20th-century thinkers. The Cambridge
philosopher G.E.
Moore (1873–1958) attempted to reconcile determinism and free
will through a conditional analysis of freedom. To say that one has acted
freely, according to Moore, is simply to say that “I should” have
acted otherwise “if I had chosen” to do so, or “if I had
performed a certain act of will, I should have done
something which I did not do.” The fact that one may not have been in a
position to choose otherwise does not undermine one’s free agency. But what
does it mean to say that one could have done otherwise? In “Freedom and
Necessity” (1946), A.J. Ayer
(1910–89) maintained that “to say that I could have acted otherwise is to say
that I should have acted otherwise if I had so chosen.” The ability to do
otherwise means only that if the past had been different, one might have chosen
differently. This is obviously a very weak notion of freedom, for it implies
that a choice or action can be free even though it is completely determined by
the past. It is an open question whether Ayer’s account provides a satisfactory
explanation of the intuitive
notion of free will. Supporters maintain that this is the only type of freedom
worth wanting, while detractors believe it does not come close to providing the
kind of free agency that humans desire, in part because it does not imply that
humans are morally responsible for their “free” actions.”
My
response Again, this is weak tea. We have an intuitive sense of free will, and
it is ontologically real, and is so universal among people that that is an
objective fact that the universal experience of the same subjective intuition
renders having free will actual, and thus people are responsible for what they
do and choose.
B:
“Other contemporary compatibilists have attacked the hard determinist’s
argument at a different juncture. In an influential paper, “Alternate
Possibilities and Moral Responsibility” (1969), the American philosopher Harry
Frankfurt questioned whether the ability to
do otherwise is truly necessary for freedom. Suppose that John is on his way to
a voting booth and is undecided about whether to vote for candidate A or
candidate B. Unbeknownst
to him, an evil neuroscientist has implanted in John’s brain a device that
will, if required, fire a signal that forces John to vote for candidate B. But
John decides to vote for candidate B on his own, so the device turns out to be
unnecessary. The device does not fire, so John acts freely. But John could not
have acted otherwise: if he had shown the slightest inclination toward
candidate A, the neuroscientist’s device would have made him change his mind.
This “Frankfurt-style” counterexample has proved to be quite powerful in
contemporary debates about free will. It demonstrates that being able to do
otherwise is not necessary for free agency.”
My
response: Really? we have the ability to do and choose otherwise, though
nomological determinism much dictates how our body functions.
B:
“If the ability to do otherwise is not necessary, what is? Like Hobbes and
Hume, Frankfurt locates freedom solely within the self. In “Freedom of the Will
and the Concept of a Person” (1971), he proposed that having free will is a
matter of identifying with one’s desires in a certain sense. Suppose that Jack
is a drug addict who wants to reform. He has a first-order desire for a certain
drug, but he also has a second-order desire not to desire the drug. Although
Jack does not want his first-order desire to be effective, he acts on it all
the same. Because of this inner conflict, Jack is not a free agent. Now
consider Jack’s friend Jill, who is also a drug addict. Unlike Jack, Jill has
no desire to reform. She has a first-order desire for a certain drug and a
second-order desire that her first-order desire be effective. She feels no ambivalence
at all about her drug addiction; not only does she want the drug, but she also
wants to want the drug. Jill identifies with her first-order desire in a way
that Jack does not, and therein lies her freedom.”
My
response: Free will is the ability to do otherwise, and is located in the self:
self-origination, but I like Frankfurt’s idea that we have 1st order
desires (often temptations), and we on a 2nd order of willing, give
in to them or withstand them. I see this as a sign of libertarianism not
compatibilism.
B:
“In “Freedom and Resentment” (1962), the British philosopher P.F.
Strawson (1919–2006) introduced an influential version of
compatibilism grounded in human psychology.
Strawson observed that people display emotions such as resentment, anger,
gratitude, and so on in response to the actions of others. He argued that
holding agents morally responsible for their actions is nothing more than
having such feelings, or “reactive attitudes,” toward them. The question of
whether the agents act freely matters only insofar as it affects the feelings
toward them that others may have; apart from this, freedom is beside the point.
Moreover, because people cannot help but feel reactive attitudes, no matter how
much they may try not to, they are justified in having them, whatever the truth
or falsity of determinism. (This is not to say that the specific reactive
attitude a person may have on a given occasion—of blind rage as opposed to mere
annoyance, for example—is always justified.)
Yet
it is far from clear that people are always justified in having reactive
attitudes. Pertinent information can drastically change one’s feelings toward
an agent. For example, one might become less angry with a driver who ran over a
cat if one discovers that the driver was rushing to the hospital with a
desperately ill child. One may even lose the anger altogether. Given the
enormous influence that everyday factual information has over what reactive
attitudes people have and whether they even have them, it seems unwise to treat
them as accurate barometers of moral responsibility.
Conclusion
Although
the central issues involved in the problem of free will and moral
responsibility have remained the same since ancient times, the emphasis
of the debate has changed greatly. Contemporary compatibilists in the vein of
Frankfurt and Strawson tend to argue that moral responsibility has little if
anything to do with determinism, since it arises from people’s desires and
attitudes rather than from the causal origins of their actions. Humans may not
be free to as great an extent as the intuitive notion of free will suggests,
but there is no other freedom to be had. Addressing the problem of free will
and moral responsibility requires establishing guidelines for holding people
accountable, not lunging after some impossible notion of free will.”
My
response: I do not find the arguments of Frankfurt and Strawson to be appealing
or convincing. People are free-willed so the deterministic but real, impactful
force impinging upon them, and people’s desires and attitudes also influence
choice, but, despite all prior causal inputs, the person retains to the power,
at least in part, to choose to do otherwise, and this is when and how his free
will comes into play.
B:
“Contemporary libertarians in the vein of Chisholm, on the other hand, continue
to maintain that moral responsibility requires a certain kind of robust
free will that compatibilism does not allow for. Their prime concern is to
untangle the metaphysical
issues underlying the intelligibility objection and to make room for free will
in an indeterministic world.”
My
response: As a near-zombie sort of second-hander existence (Ayn Rand’s term) as
a selfless, groupist nonindiviudator, even that sleepy robot has a modicum of
residual, stunted free will, but robust free will is had, needed, own and
demanded by an accomplished individuators cooking on all burners.
If
the monists and atheists deterministically or even indeterministically deny
that free will is the reality for each human being, give me a chance to train 5
million children to maverize, and that would be powerful, transformative,
empirical proof that they are free, choosing otherwise as they wish, and are
robustly free.
It
is easy for the skeptics about free will to deny its existence, and the
existence of God, when 94% of people stumble around sleepily and incoherently
every day as nonindividuators, barely able to put two sentences together let
alone plan and run their own individual lives.
B:
“How much of human
behaviour is determined by past events, and
how much does this matter—if it does matter—for free will and moral
responsibility? In the end, the important question may be not whether the
universe is deterministic or indeterministic but whether one is willing to accept
a definition of free will that is much weaker than intuition
demands . . . .
G.E.
Moore G.E. Moore, detail of a pencil drawing by William Orpen; in
the National Portrait Gallery, London.”
My response: As a dualistic and free will anti-skeptic, I
renounced any attempt to offer a water-down version of free will, which exists
in the life on joiner/nonindividuator with a stunted personal consciousness,
but, robust free will is her potential and telos if she wills it to be made
creative, original, brilliant, artistic and powerful--if she elects to actuate
her potential and an individuating loner, with her consciousness made smart,
strong, vibrant and ever-developing, and she cares not, as an individuator,
brushing aside any flimsy intelligibility objection, that both determinism,
indeterminism, chance and luck all rule her, that her will is never free not
matter the preceding or current inputs. Her life of successful, self-directed
beautiful personhood as a great soul gives the lie to all this nonsense. She is
free because she knows that natural and social forces, some deterministic in
nature and some indeterministic in nature, some forces without cause, some that
are stochastic and some that are lucky for her, they all influence her, but she
as she grows as a living angel, is a moral, powerful consciousness in the
world, and she is the source of her choices and actions, and she is willful
enough to be causal and make her intentions heard, all inputs to the contrary.
B: “determinism
determinism,
in philosophy
and science,
the thesis
that all events in the universe, including human decisions and actions, are
causally inevitable. Determinism entails that, in a situation in which a person
makes a certain decision or performs a certain action, it is impossible that he
or she could have made any other decision or performed any other action. In
other words, it is never true that people could have decided or acted otherwise
than they actually did.
Determinism
in this sense is usually understood to be incompatible with free will,
or the supposed power or capacity
of humans to make decisions or perform actions independently of any prior event
or state of the universe. Philosophers and scientists who deny the existence
of free will on this basis are known as “hard” determinists.
In
contrast, so-called “soft” determinists, also called compatibilists, believe
that determinism and free will are compatible after all. In most cases, soft
determinists attempt to achieve this reconciliation by subtly revising or
weakening the commonsense notion of free will.”
My
response: Determinism and free will are never entirely incompatible, but they
are proportionately incompatible with the human child (at birth, being mostly
other willed in natural and social inputs, but latently, modestly free-willing
from birth); the child or nonindividuating, group-living, altruist morality
driven, group-identifying adult submersed in the herd is determined mostly. His
latent, robust free will remains suppressed under the weight of all the forces
holding him back an down in darkness, slavery, superstition, evil and self-loathing.
Free
will and determinism and free will and indeterminism (His will gets freer, stronger,
and faster as he maverizes.) can all be made compatible, but his will gets
freer, faster and deeper under indeterminism than under the pressure exerted
upon him by deterministic forces.
Both
deterministic and indeterministic stimuli can become more compatible as he individuates
(His strengthened free will, so self-determining and powerful now, takes the
lead as he molds deterministic inputs to suit his will and free choices. His consciousness/soul/mind
grows and gets smarter and more original thinking and self-causal; his free
will is now compatible with the deterministic indeterministic and random
influences bombarding him as he reacts to them as they influence him. He chooses
how he will react, live and what goal he shall creatively, morally forcefully impose
upon reality in response to all these felt influences.
Robust free will becomes compatible with determinism,
as the individuator comes to control his influences. He shapes, redirects, and
unnaturally repositions such inputs to make the world, as far as he can, be how
he wants it to be—he does alter reality that is always altering him, and the
sometimes cooperative and often competitive clash of opposing forces allows him
to create love grow and innovate and that is his response and action in
reaction against incoming deterministic and random influences.
B: “Contemporary soft determinists have
included the English philosopher G.E. Moore
(1873–1958), who held that acting freely means only that one would have acted
otherwise had one decided to do so (even if, in fact, one could not have
decided to do so), and the American philosopher Harry Frankfurt, who argued
that acting freely amounts to identifying with or approving of one’s own
desires (even if those desires are such that one cannot help but act on them).
The
extreme alternative
to determinism is indeterminism,
the view that at least some events have no deterministic cause but occur
randomly, or by chance. Indeterminism is supported to some extent by research
in quantum
mechanics, which suggests that some events at
the quantum
level are in principle unpredictable (and therefore random). Philosophers and
scientists who believe that the universe is indeterministic and that humans
possess free will are known as “libertarians” (libertarianism in this sense is
not to be confused with the school of political
philosophy called libertarianism).
Although it is possible to hold that the universe is indeterministic and that
human actions are nevertheless determined, few contemporary philosophers defend
this view.
Libertarianism
is vulnerable
to what is called the “intelligibility” objection, which points out that people
can have no more control over a purely random action than they have over an
action that is deterministically inevitable; in neither case does free will
enter the picture. Hence, if human actions are indeterministic, free will does
not exist.”
The
Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica This article was most recently
revised and updated by Brian
Duignan.
Philosophy
& Religion Philosophical
Issues . . . “
B: ‘free will
free will, in philosophy
and science,
the supposed power or capacity of humans to make decisions or perform actions
independently of any prior event or state of the universe. Arguments for free
will have been based on the subjective experience of freedom, on sentiments
of guilt, on revealed religion,
and on the common assumption of individual moral
responsibility that underlies the concepts of law,
reward, punishment, and incentive. In theology,
the existence
of free will must be reconciled
with God’s omniscience and benevolence
and with divine grace,
which allegedly is necessary for any meritorious act.”
My response: Free will is the power or capacity of humans to
make decisions or perform actions sometimes independently of any prior event or
state of the universe—especially if individuating agent displays an
impressively powerful, ingenious free-willing ability--, sometimes the power is
weaker and less free if the person is less individuated or self-causal, and
sometimes the person is so insensate and low-functioning as a primitive,
conformist nonindividuator that her
free-willing capacity is reduced right down to the minimal free will spark
which she and all have at birth, a spark never developed any farther by her,
though it is not utterly snuffed out in theory or practice, but the next thing
to it. As a blighted zombie, she will react to more than interject her will
upon incoming inputs.
B: “A prominent feature of existentialism
is the concept of a radical, perpetual, and frequently agonizing freedom of choice.
Jean-Paul
Sartre (1905–80), for example, spoke of the individual “condemned
to be free.””
My response: I like this exceptionally robust or radical
freedom of choice so popular among existentialists, but it is likely only or
usually possessed and wielded by rational individuators.
B:
“The existence of free will is denied by some proponents of determinism,
the thesis that every event in the universe is causally inevitable. Determinism
entails that, in a situation in which people make a certain decision or perform
a certain action, it is impossible that they could have made any other decision
or performed any other action. In other words, it is never true that people
could have decided or acted otherwise than they actually did. Philosophers and
scientists who believe that determinism in this sense is incompatible with free
will are known as “hard” determinists.
In
contrast, so-called “soft” determinists, also called compatibilists, believe
that determinism and free will are compatible
after all. In most cases, soft determinists attempt to achieve this
reconciliation by subtly revising or weakening the commonsense notion of free
will.”
My
response: I will call myself a libertarian compatibilist. My first
presupposition is that human nature is dual: part
material/biological/determined (we are mostly determined, especially in our
nonindividuated state, our natural state at birth) and part spiritual/mental
consciousness, free or self-determining (mostly an achieved status of a
robustly held and fielded free will, acting upon the world while it acts upon
oneself).
The
soft determinists promote a misleading compatibilism in which they reconcile a
pathetic, wimpy personal free made compatible with nomological determinism by
weakening the commonsense notion of free will.
I
retain the powerful sense of free will, and make
determinism/indeterminism/chance compatible with the free will by having the self-consciously,
innovatively, deliberately and fearlessly receive and acknowledge these
incoming influences and then self-determine how to respond in new new and
meaningful ways so choices taken and actions undertaken reveal the will of the
responder as he operates in the world, remaking it in his own image—as long as this
image is coherent with God’s image of Deself and how the world should evolve.
B:
“Contemporary soft determinists have included the English philosopher G.E. Moore
(1873–1958), who held that acting freely means only that one would have acted
otherwise had one decided to do so (even if, in fact, one could not have
decided to do so), and the American philosopher Harry
Frankfurt (born 1929), who has argued that
acting freely amounts to identifying with or approving of one’s own desires
(even if those desires are such that one cannot help but act on them). . . . “
B:
“The extreme alternative
to determinism is indeterminism,
the view that at least some events have no deterministic cause but occur
randomly, or by chance. Indeterminism is supported to some extent by research
in quantum
mechanics, which suggests that some events at
the quantum
level are in principle unpredictable (and therefore random). Philosophers and
scientists who believe that the universe is indeterministic and that humans
possess free will are known as “libertarians” (libertarianism in this sense is
not to be confused with the school of political
philosophy called libertarianism).
Although it is possible to hold that the universe is indeterministic and that
human actions are nevertheless determined, few contemporary philosophers defend
this view.
Libertarianism
is vulnerable
to what is called the “intelligibility” objection, which points out that people
can have no more control over a purely random action than they have over an
action that is deterministically inevitable; in neither case does free will
enter the picture. Hence, if human actions are indeterministic, free will does
not exist. See also free
will and moral responsibility.”
My
response: My response: God made each of us in De’s image, so this divine spark
in us is our hint from God to emulate God by assuming the godly role and
responsibility of living as a Creator/Individuator/Self-Determining Cosmos
Builder and Maintainer—that is our God-given telos on earth. Such an
accomplished winner human being is rather robustly free willing and adept at
dealing with and sublimating her determinants into love, art, logic, invention,
and mathematics, expressing her reaction to all indeterministic and
deterministic nudges. It matters not whether the intelligibility objection
holds water or not, she as a developing maverick dominates or strenuously, atavistically
strives or does imposes her will upon all incoming influences, not vice versa,
be they necessitated or random.
B: “The
Editors of Encyclopaedia BritannicaThis article was most recently
revised and updated by Brian
Duignan.
Philosophy
& Religion Religious
Beliefs . . .”
B: “problem
of evil
theology
Written by
problem
of evil, problem in theology
and the philosophy
of religion that arises for any view that
affirms the following three propositions: God is almighty,
God is perfectly good, and evil exists.
The problem
An
important statement of the problem of evil, attributed to Epicurus,
was cited by the Scottish philosopher David Hume
in his Dialogues
Concerning Natural Religion (1779): “Is [God] willing to
prevent evil, but not able? then is he impotent. Is he able, but not willing?
then is he malevolent. Is he both able and willing? whence then is evil?” Since
well before Hume’s time, the problem has been the basis of a positive argument
for atheism:
If God
exists, then he is omnipotent
and perfectly good; a perfectly good being would eliminate evil as far as it
could; there is no limit to what an omnipotent being can do; therefore, if God
exists, there would be no evil in the world; there is evil in the world;
therefore, God does not exist. In this argument and in the problem of evil
itself, evil is understood to encompass
both moral evil (caused by free human actions) and natural evil (caused by
natural phenomena such as disease, earthquakes, and floods).
Most
thinkers, however, have found this argument too simple, since it does not
recognize cases in which eliminating one evil causes another to arise or in
which the existence of a particular evil entails some good state of affairs
that morally outweighs it. Moreover, there may be logical limits to what an
omnipotent being can or cannot do. Most skeptics, therefore, have taken the
reality of evil as evidence that God’s existence is unlikely rather than
impossible. Often the reality of evil is treated as canceling out whatever
evidence there may be that God exists—e.g., as set forth in the argument
from design, which is based on an analogy
between the apparent design discerned in the cosmos and the design involved in
human artifacts.
Thus, Hume devotes much of the earlier parts of his Dialogues to
attacking the argument from design, which was popular in the 18th century. In
later parts of the work, he discusses the problem of evil and concludes by
arguing after all that the mixed evidence available supports the existence of a
divine designer of the world, but only one who is morally neutral and not the
God of traditional theistic
religions.”
My
response: I confess that if God is all-powerful, all-loving, all-good,
all-knowing, and omnipresent, it is hard to explain why evil exists, and yet
people have free will and are responsible for their sins.
Part
of the answer is that there may be logical limits to what an omnipotent being
can or cannot do as listed above. I could argue that Fate is all good and all
evil, all-knowing and all-evil; consequently, that is the source of that evil
exists (It may not satisfactorily explain why evil exists.); despite suffering in
the world, somehow people are more
responsible than not for their choices and actions.
I
believe we are free, and that that is not just a subjective, mass hysteria of
self-deluding by 7 billion human puppets. I know we are free but I cannot prove
it—this mystery is what I say it is-- and the free will skeptics cannot
disprove it, so I will act as if God exists, and does not play games with
humans, and that we are free, accountable and will be held to account in this
world and the next for how we choose and act. That we are free and that God
allows us to be free with no tricks and no mind-games going on is an article of
faith for me; that is the best I can construe of the ancient paradoxes, and I
may not every make any headway beyond this dissatisfying conclusion It would be
rewarding to know for sure if people have free will or not, but I feel quite
deeply that they are.
B:
“. . .
Theistic responses
Religious
believers have had recourse
to two main strategies. One approach is to offer a theodicy,
an account of why God chooses to permit evil in the world (and why he is
morally justified in so choosing)—e.g., that it is a necessary consequence of sin
or that, as Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz claimed, this is the “best
of all possible worlds.” The other approach is to attempt
a more limited “defense,” which does not aim to explain God’s purposes but
merely to show that the existence of at least some evil in the world is
logically compatible with God’s goodness, power, and wisdom. Many philosophers
and theologians have rejected accounts of the first kind as inherently
implausible or as foolhardy attempts to go beyond the bounds of human knowledge
to discern
God’s inscrutable purposes.”
My
response: The Father and Mother encourage us to speculate about wildly
open-ended metaphysical questions, including devising theodicies of various
degrees of plausibility.
I
caution that people should be respectful and good deities and not blasphemous
when trying to create a story that explains these ultimate issues.
It
seems as if God’s purposes remain somewhat inscrutable to us, and somehow that
the presence of evil in the world is compatible with God love of goodness,
moral and spiritual goodness/
B:
“A variety of arguments have been offered in response to the problem of evil,
and some of them have been used in both theodicies and defenses. One argument,
known as the free
will defense, claims that evil is caused not by God but by human
beings, who must be allowed to choose evil if they are to have free will.”
My
response: It is silly to think that humans, a created and sinful creature by
nature, could create or cause evil in the world, though when sinning and filled
with malice, we do often create, cause, and expand evil in the world during our
short lives, but evil is a primeval, eternal force which was here before humans
were created, and will be here to belabor future intelligent beings with free
wills and moral accountability burdens long after humans have vanished from the
face of the earth.
Either
evil always was, or it was created by a powerful gods, and that may be Satan
and Lera, but Fate is the world and chief deity beyond good (The Father and The
Mother) and beyond evil (Satan and Lera). These deep metaphysical questions are
such that we cannot atomistically or collectively or definitively answer at
this point.
B: “This response presupposes that humans are
indeed free, and it fails to reckon with natural evil, except insofar as the
latter is increased by human factors such as greed or thoughtlessness. Another
argument, developed by the English philosopher Richard
Swinburne, is that natural evils can be the
means of learning and maturing. Natural evils, in other words, can help cultivate
virtues such as courage and generosity by forcing humans to confront danger,
hardship, and need. Such arguments are commonly supplemented by appeals to
belief in a life
after death, not just as reward or compensation
but as the state in which the point of human suffering and the way in which God
brings good out of evil will be made clear.”
My
response: It seems as if both the presence of natural evil and malevolent evil
in the world do teach the good and just be better themselves morally and
spiritually, if they stay at it, but beyond that simple beneficial presence of
these evil, they grow violence, suffering hatred and destruction in the world,
and benefit no one.
B:
“ Since many theodicies seem limited (because one can easily imagine a better
world), and since many thinkers have not been convinced by the argument that
the reality of evil establishes atheism, it is likely that future discussions
will attempt to balance the reality of evil against evidence in favour of the existence
of God.”