Wednesday, July 30, 2025

Exodus 35:30-35

 

In Exodus 35, Moses calls for experts among the Hebrews to come forth and build the Dwelling, the tabernacle, the ark of the covenant to hold the Ten Commandments, with a mercy seat or throne where invisible Yahweh would sit and receive His people.

 

Just think about that, that God will sit in a chair and receive human visitors. Wow, if our faith was strong enough, that God would reward us by sitting in a chair and indicate De’s willingness to receive us.

 

Here is what is written in The New American Bible: “The Artisans. Moses said to the Israelites, ‘See, the Lord has chosen Bezalel, son of Uri, son of Hur, of the tribe of Judah, and has filled him with a divine spirit of skill and understanding of every craft:”

 

My response: What fascinates me here is that this is the first and perhaps only Biblical account which I know of expressing how God provide a divine spirit of skill and understanding of every craft so that Bezalel, his artisan, could devise and construct finished products of unparalleled beauty, utility and an artistic highlighting of God presence, glory, and greatness.

 

Such an artistic, immensely skilled artisan would need to, of his own free will, agree to answer God’s calling to produce things of beauty as requested by God, and this artisan would be an individuators of high rank and ability.

 

Here is Biblical evidence that Yahweh, Individuator, Creator and Master Engineer, Artisan, Artist, and Craftsman, blesses and enters the heart, mind, and soul of the willing, participating individuator, the human willing to live, act, work and construct in God’s image and likeness. I find it exhilarating and inspiring.

 

If one wills to maverize and requests divine help and blessing from the Good Spirits to become a fellow indiviudator, then the creative spirit will flow through to incipient individuator as exemplified here in Exodus as Yahweh filled Bezalel with the divine spirit of skill and understanding.

 

New American Bible: “in the production of embroidery, in making things of gold, silver and bronze, in cutting and mounting special stones, in carving wood and every other craft.”

 

My response: It occurs to me too that Yahweh was not against human luxury, ornate products and works of beauty as vanity and materialism, but as a human, crafted display the glory of God and the cosmos, especially when crafted intentionally to glorify the Creator and De’s universe.

 

New American Bible: He has also given both him and Oholiab, son of Ahisamach, of the tribe of Dan, the ability to teach others. He has endowed them with skill to execute all types of work: engraving, embroidering, the making of variegated cloth of violet, purple and scarlet yarn and fine linen thread, weaving, and all other arts and crafts.”

 

My response: God is most willing to assist us in growing as artists, thinkers, writers, poets, technicians, inventors, mechanics, and artisans of every description if we would but try on our own, while inviting the Good Spirits to enter us, inflame our imagination and creative juices, to stir in us the desire to create, build, construct.

 

Here are these same lines from the Holy Bible (KJV): “And Moses said unto the children of Israel, See, the Lord hath called by name Bezaleel the son of Uri, the son of Hur, of the tribe of Judah. And he hath filled him with the spirit of God, in wisdom, in understanding, and in knowledge, in all manner of workmanship;”

 

My response: If the Divine Couple, Jesus or another good deity or the Good Spirits announce to the world, naming you specifically as anointed and selected, called to maverize in some singular, brilliant way, will you answer gladly the summons to duty, to bring beauty, cosmos and justice into the world, and will you allow the Good Spirits to enter you, filling you with their aura and energy, so all manners of wisdom, understanding, and knowledge of all manners of workmanship are made available to you?

 

Holy Bible: “And to devise curious works, to work in gold, and in silver, and in brass, And in the cutting of stones, to set them, and in carving of wood, to make any manner of cunning work, And he hath put in his heart that he may teach, both he, and Aholiab, the son of Ahisamach, of the tribe of Dan.

 

Them he hath filled with wisdom of the heart, to work all manner of work, of the engraver, and of the cunning workman, and of the embroiderer, in blue, and in purple, in scarlet, and in fine linen, and of the weaver, even of them that do any work and of those that devise cunning work.”

 

My response: Invite God to fill your heart with the creative impulse, and the ability to actualize your potential and ambition.

 

Individuate and be proud of what you have wrought, but, not so proud as to fail to attribute to the good deities, your thanks and allegiance, that they are the source of your creative imagination, and you must create and make to glorify God, not compete with God, as humans foolishly did by building the tower of Babel.

Tuesday, July 29, 2025

Amereica & Shariah Law

 

I received an email on my phone from PNW, which is apparently an online Christian news source. They wrote an excellent article about the dangers of shariah law coming to America, so I copy and pasting a paragraph from their website where they describe their mission and identity, and then below that is the article in its entirety, which I will respond too. Here is the website blurb first:

 

I copied these articles on 7/29/25 and they were likely posted the same day:

 

 

“Prophecy News Watch provided by Worthy Ministries

Prophecy News Watch is a service hosted by Worthy Ministries to provide Christians daily news from a Biblical, and yet Prophetic worldview. Our news is gathered by our Christian News Service, Worthy News. For more about our vision for how we assemble our daily headlines, please read, "What is Worthy News?"”

 

My response: Here is their article.

PNW: “Sharia Rising: Islam's Quiet Takeover Of London And New York

By PNW Staff July 29, 2025


It's no longer theory. It's no longer rumor. The Islamization of our major cities is happening--aggressively, publicly, and without apology. From taxpayer-funded Sharia positions in the UK to chants of "Globalize the Intifada" on the streets of New York, the message is clear: many Muslims are not merely seeking to assimilate--they're seeking to dominate.”

 

My response: Those who misunderstand and underestimate the fierce, fearsome, impressive, ageless, ambitious, unyielding ambition of the leaders of Islam to spread their caliphate and shariah law across the planet, know not this implacable foe of the West.

 

Muslims, even if defeated and quiet for centuries, never assimilate; rather they dominate and force the country they have immigrated into or militarily attacked to wholly, permanently submit to their domination or hegemony, or be put to the sword or endlessly be warred against by these theocratic true believers and aggressors.

 

Islam is an ancient mass movement, sometimes quiescent, sometimes stirring, sometimes revolutionary, always seeking world domination, world conquering, theocratic totalitarianism at its worst.

 

Islam per se need not be an evil faith, but without, from a majority of its adherents, a proclaimed,  serious, significant, open confession that its form breeds evil, tyranny, war, violence and malevolence in the world in its present form, it is the most evil faith on earth.

 

They are publicly and unapologetically voicing their intentions now in London and New York, and they mean what they say, and follow through with it. They are willful and unrelenting, and this makes them exceedingly dangerous and potentially violent. They are the enemies of the West, so the West must not allow them to—any more of them—to come to America.

 

Its adherents must work, the majority of them, to moderate, modernize, and demilitarize Islam by with an admixture of moderate Mavellonialist and Western values, and then it in its updated, modified form, will be as gentle and harmless and benevolent as Christian, Judaism or Buddhism.

 

PNW: “For decades, critics were shouted down for warning that open-door immigration and unchecked multiculturalism would invite a clash of civilizations. Now, the clash has arrived. And our leaders are still asleep.”

 

My response: They got here and grow strong here due to the generosity and foolish trust from liberals and Leftists, but they grew strong under the guise of multiculturalism, but they always were cultural monoculturalists, and now that is realized as they come out into the open, and the clash of our civilizations is building, and still the politicians let it happen.

 

PNW: “What Is Sharia--and Why It Threatens Everything We Believe

 

Sharia Law is not some spiritual discipline or optional religious code. It is a comprehensive legal system that governs criminal justice, civil law, family law, business, and personal conduct--based entirely on Islamic texts. It is totalitarian by nature, declaring that man's law must bow to Allah's.”

 

My response: These PNW staff writers know what shariah law is, and it cannot gain a toehold anywhere in America.

 

PNW: “Under Sharia, women are subjugated, apostates are executed, blasphemy is criminalized, non-Muslims are treated as second-class, and free speech is silenced. There is no room for compromise with the Western ideals of liberty, equality under the law, and religious freedom. Sharia is not compatible with our Constitution--it is its antithesis.”

 

My response: In this paragraph above, the writers ably describe what Shariah is, and it is the antithesis to a people enjoying their human and natural rights, liberty, and Western constitutional republicanism.

 

PNW: “And yet, a shocking number of Muslims--even in Western democracies--want it.

 

In a 2024 poll by the Henry Jackson Society, 32% of British Muslims said they support implementing Sharia law in the UK. A full one-third of those living in a supposedly free country are willing to abandon its freedoms to install religious rule. And they are not hiding their intentions.

 

Sharia in the Streets--and Now in Government Job Postings

 

The UK just narrowly avoided an unthinkable milestone. In July 2025, a job listing appeared on the British government's employment site for a Sharia Legal Assistant--paid by taxpayer funds. The role? Supporting the Manchester Sharia Council, a group that openly rules on family and domestic matters under Islamic law.

 

"By the will of Allah," the job description reads, "we ensure a positive and desired outcome."

 

Let that sink in: the British government nearly funded a parallel Islamic court system. One law for Muslims, another for everyone else.

 

Though public backlash forced the listing down, the damage is done. The infrastructure of Sharia is already there: 85 Sharia councils operating across England, a growing number of Muslim-led community groups, and support from leftist politicians who care more about "diversity" than about defending their own civilization.”

 

My response: Islam under the cover of diversity will destroy England, and it is working its way towards control of America, and its invasion and conservative revolution here is in its infancy, so it must be stopped before it gains strength. We must defend our civilization.

 

I want no pogroms here against citizen Muslims. I want no persecution, discrimination against them, no denying their right to worship as they will, but nowhere should shariah law ever be allowed.

 

We should dialogue with American Muslims to modernize, moderate, and demilitarize their fanatical faith, and almost no immigration of Muslims can be allowed here anymore.

 

PNW: “Meanwhile, Islam is growing rapidly. The most popular name for baby boys in London is now Mohammed. The number of mosques has exploded, and over 6.5% of the UK population now identifies as Muslim, with concentrations over 30% in parts of Birmingham and East London. The transformation is cultural, demographic, and soon, legal--unless it is stopped.”

 

 

My response: This article is so well written. First, Muslims immigrate into a country. Then they grow in numbers and influence. Now, feeling their oats, they start dominating and grabbing power, forcing the transformation into their adopted country, but not adopting its culture and religion; they transform and dominate demographically, culturally, and they anticipate, one day legally.

 

Muslims have high birth rates, and they can breed us out, to put it crudely. Americans have a fertility rate of 1.6; Americans and whites need to have more babies and fewer abortions.



 

PNW: “Islamic Power on Display in New York City

 

Across the Atlantic, New York isn't faring any better.

 

Muslim protesters recently shut down the Belt Parkway, a major NYC highway, exiting their cars to chant "Globalize the Intifada"--a violent rallying cry associated with terror campaigns against Jews.

 

This didn't happen in Kabul. It didn't happen in Tehran. It happened in Brooklyn--home to nearly half a million Jews--as a group of radicalized demonstrators stood on American soil and called for global jihad.

 

Let's stop calling this "protest." It's open intimidation. It's a warning. And it's only growing bolder.”

 

My response: If and when radicalized young Muslims riot, threaten Jews, break the law or close highways, arrest them promptly, try them and jail them. Zero tolerance for these violent haters and theocratically revolutionary fanatics.

 

PNW: “New York now has 275-300 mosques, many of them packed daily. An estimated 750,000 Muslims live in NYC, making up 9% of the city's population and representing 22% of the entire U.S. Muslim population. Thousands have gathered in Times Square for mass Islamic prayers--a public declaration of faith, dominance, and presence.

 

And if far-left Democrat Zohran Mamdani--a state assemblyman who defends anti-Israel rhetoric and refuses to condemn chants like "Globalize the Intifada"--continues his political rise, New York's Islamization will only accelerate. His potential path to the governorship is not just a political concern--it's a civilizational threat.

 

This Is Not Assimilation--It Is a Parallel Civilization.”

 

My response: I must use my words carefully. Islam as a parallel civilization is an evil, totalitarian, vicious, inferior civilization to Western democracy and capitalism. I do not want to change the theology of the worshipers, but their legal code, their cultural and political solutions must be abandoned by them, should they want to stay in the West and assimilate into the West, and this assimilation must be mandatory—again, not theologically, but legally and culturally as they moderate, modernize, and demilitarize as they live in Western nations.

 

PNW: “Let's be clear: the issue is not that Muslims are growing in number. The issue is that a growing number within that population want to replace our laws with theirs.

 

This is a religious ideology that seeks to shape every aspect of society: from law and education to diet, media, and marriage. Its adherents don't want a "seat at the table." They want to build a new table, governed by Sharia, ruled by imams, and submitted to Islamic norms.”

 

My response: Congress needs to pass a law banning shariah law ever being practiced and enforced anywhere in continental US, as blatantly unconstitutional and anti-American.

 

PNW: “They are not hiding their goals. And yet Western politicians, clergy, and media refuse to listen.

 

Worse, they vilify anyone who does.

 

Critics are branded "Islamophobic," "racist," or "xenophobic"--as if warning about the collapse of your own civilization is somehow immoral. But what is truly immoral is to stand by while your children inherit a nation that no longer reflects the values you were raised with.”

 

My response: Yeah, yeah, socialists, Democrats, liberals and Leftists abuse critics of Islam and shariah law as fascist, Christian nationalists, as Islamophobic, racist and xenophobic, and, there may be a trace of that, but, in the main Islam, not as a theology and faith, but as a cultural, social and legal system, is evil and vicious, and cannot legally or socially be allowed to grow and spread in America. We have the most beautiful values in the world here in America, and be damned if we will let invaders take it away from us: love us and assimilate, or get out. We will not allow you to dominate us, ever. Never, never.

 

PNW: “Judeo-Christian Civilization Is Not Optional--It's Foundational”

 

My response: Judeo-Christian Civilization is not optional—it is foundational. It is for two reasons: first our Greek heritage and our Judeo-Christian heritage gave us Western civilization, the Modernistic civilization fit for the future, so it must be preserved and extended.

 

Second, Jesus died on the Cross to save people, as individuals, or as humanity as indiviuals. It is not the Irish group, nor the Saudi Arabian group, nor the Nigerian group, as tribes, whose souls were saved by Jesus. It was the soul of one sinner at a time, as an individual; we go to heaven or hell or purgatory, as an isolated, atomized individual, and I regard this ancient basis for individual spiritual salvation to extend to ethical salvation—which is part makes spiritual salvation achievable—because the egoistic-indvidualistic indiviudator usually will love the self, and everything else throughs self-love, and then moral goodness grow in the agent’s will, nudging her to seek reconciliation with Jesus or another benevolent deity, to transform her sinner’s soul into a spiritually healthy soul.

 

PNW: “This isn't about nostalgia. It's about survival. The Judeo-Christian foundation of our laws, freedoms, and moral order cannot coexist with Sharia. One must prevail over the other.

 

The hard truth? Islam is growing. Christians are shrinking. Muslims are mobilizing. Christians are compromising. And if that doesn't change, the West as we know it will not survive.”

 

My response: The writers at PNW are truth-writers. Islam is growing and Christianity is shrinking. Muslims are mobilizing, and Christians are jaded, demoralized, secularized, disengaged and compromising.

 

If we are not careful and wake up and counter-mobilize against Muslims pretty quick, American will be what London has degraded into being.

 

If Muslims succeed and set up a worldwide caliphate with shariah law as the law of every land, then the Reign of the Beast has arrived.

 

Most religions, however small or worldwide, start out naturally fanatical, tyrannical, and willing to use violence to force conversions, or at curb or wipe out religious rivals. Since the religious wars in Europe, especially with liberal thinkers like John Locke, Christianity started down the path towards modernizing, moderating and hopefully demilitarizing.

 

This modernization and moderation adjustment is one that Islam and the Islamists have never undertaken, and the world can be wiped out unless they make this journey willingly an soon. This Muslims must do, to escape holding the dishonor of being the most savage, evil, violent religion currently on the world stage.

Top of Form

Bottom of Form

 

© 2025 Prophecy News Watch. All Rights Reserved.
Located in Coeur D Alene, Idaho - USA.
Call Toll Free: 1-877-561-4442
Email: Info@ProphecyNewsWatch.com
 
Visit us on social media.  

 
 

 

Sunday, July 27, 2025

Exodus 34: 29-30

 

I will print out two verses from Exodus which describes how Moses visited the Lord on Mount Sinai and came down with The Ten Commandments written on two tablets and his face was radiant and scary to the Hebrews for Moses had for 40 days been conversing with and in the presence of Yahweh.

 

These verses are remarkable in two ways. First, Moses was instructed by God to write down a moral code for the masses of Israel to live by. That a major Divinity would provide people with a moral code is a remarkable act, for it indicates that people are born sinners, and require ethical and spiritual reformation to be allowed to go to heaven.

 

Anyone seeking to dismiss the importance of The Ten Commandments is a fool.

 

Second, it is astounding that Moses spent time with God, so that his face was radiant as a consequence; that this godly aura accompanied a man of God is impressive, and that it was scary and somehow offensive to regular people does indicate that people travel not with God, nor converse with God easily or naturally.

 

Here are the two verses from The New American Bible: “As Moses came down from Mount Sinai with the two tablets of the commandments in his hands, he did not know that the skin of his face had become radiant while he conversed with the Lord. When, Aaron then, and the other Israelites saw Moses and noticed how radiant the skin of his face had become, they were afraid to come near him.”

 

Here are these same two verses from the Holy Bible (KJV): “And it came to pass, when Moses came down from mount Sinai with the two tablets of testimony in Moses’ hand, when he came down from the mount, that Moses wist not that the skin of his face shone when talked with him.

 

And when Moses and all the children of Israel saw Moses, behold, the skin of his face shone; and they were afraid to come nigh him..”

 

 

Exodus 34:29--30

 

I will print out two verses from Exodus which describes how Moses visited the Lord on Mount Sinai and came down with The Ten Commandments written on two tablets and his face was radiant and scary to the Hebrews for Moses had for 40 days been conversing with and in the presence of Yahweh.

 

These verses are remarkable in two ways. First, Moses was instructed by God to write down a moral code for the masses of Israel to live by. That a major Divinity would provide people with a moral code is a remarkable act, for it indicates that people are born sinners, and require ethical and spiritual reformation to be allowed to go to heaven.

 

Anyone seeking to dismiss the importance of The Ten Commandments is a fool.

 

Second, it is astounding that Moses spent time with God, so that his face was radiant as a consequence; that this godly aura accompanied a man of God is impressive, and that it was scary and somehow offensive to regular people does indicate that people travel not with God, nor converse with God easily or naturally.

 

Here are the two verses from The New American Bible: “As Moses came down from Mount Sinai with the two tablets of the commandments in his hands, he did not know that the skin of his face had become radiant while he conversed with the Lord. When, Aaron then, and the other Israelites saw Moses and noticed how radiant the skin of his face had become, they were afraid to come near him.”

 

Here are these same two verses from the Holy Bible (KJV): “And it came to pass, when Moses came down from mount Sinai with the two tablets of testimony in Moses’ hand, when he came down from the mount, that Moses wist not that the skin of his face shone when talked with him.

 

And when Moses and all the children of Israel saw Moses, behold, the skin of his face shone; and they were afraid to come nigh him..”

 

 

Exodus 34:21

 

It occurred to me that there are many proofs in ancient religious texts that indicate that the law of moderation was one of the axiomatic moral requirements that the benevolent deities laid down for their worshipers. I find one such proof in this verse from Exodus, as translated in The New America Bible: “For six days you may work, but on the seventh day you shall rest; on that day you must rest even during the season of plowing and harvest.”

 

My response: We are to work six days a week, but rest on the seventh day; working is a requirement for humans over 80% of the time, but we need to rest and play too.  God commands it of us.

 

Here is this same verse from the Holy Bible (KJV): “Six days thou shalt work, but on the seventh day thou shalt rest: in earing time and in harvest thou shalt rest.”

 

My response: Note that God urges us to work most of the time so working is how we provide for our families and ourselves, and working provide an adult with meaning, satisfaction, structure, and something to do.

Exodus 34:20

 

In Exodus 34, Yahweh instructs the Hebrews not to appear before Him emptyhanded. Here is that line from The New American Bible: “’No one shall appear before me emptyhanded.’”

 

My response: Now this can be read literally to mean that no one, however poor, should appear before Yahweh in the temple with no gift of offering to share, even if the gift shared was wildflowers from a nearby meadow, fresh water from a mountain stream, or a pretty quartz rock chunk offered to Yahweh.

 

The gift for the poor, or anyone, I suppose, can be a joyous, prayerful offering, and God would like and accept that.

 

Here is that same line from the Holy Bible (KJV): “And none shall appear before me empty.”

Saturday, July 26, 2025

Peterson On Evil Intelligence

 

 

 

                                                                        A

 

 

I recently listened to and took notes on a 5.42-minute video snippet, narrated by Jordan Peterson. I write out what he said below with some slight editing. The title of the video is When High IQ turns Luciferian. This clip was made in December 2024. I will lay out his video which, lightly edited by me, and then response to it. Here it is.

 

Jordan (J after this): “If you look at personality attributes, the two or three that you would associate, like say with morality. Like it is tricky and there’s not a one-to-one relationship, and I’m not implying that. But, generally speaking, people regard those who are conscientious, diligent, hardworking, reliable, industrious as moral.

 

Now, that’s not the only dimension of morality because you have agreeableness. And more people who are more agreeable in our society at least are deemed more moral, because they are more caring, they’re more empathic, they’re more polite.

 

And so you could even see conscientiousness as the conservative virtue and agreeableness as the liberal virtue if you wanted to. It doesn’t matter. Those are the places where virtue seems to be captured to some degree in the personality models.”

 

There is zero correlation with IQ.”

 

My response: I intuitively cannot buy this conclusion of his that IQ correlates not at all to being virtuous or moral.

 

My hunch is that reasoning more than feeling is how humans act well, that godly individuators, agents with high IQs, natural or unleashed spiritually, will be egoists and individualists, and one cannot be a well-developed moral person, without intellect figuring deeply and inextricably into the equation. I will seek to prove this.

 

 I will have to ponder on it and see how IQ is virtuous, because humans morally and scientifically advance and progress best when people reason, ponder, create, and discover, so IQ is moral. Somehow it is tied into the agent’s good will, for reason is an instrumental servant of a good will, but the will is intelligent consciousness. As a result, reason, not just feeling and passion, is a motivating will of force.

 

It seems that emotionally willing, instinct and desire are the primary motivators and rulers of  us as lower level consciousnesses with minimal free will excrcised per capita, as group-living agents, altruistic and selfless; as we maverize as rational individuals, then our reason increasingly is resorted to by us, not only for instrumental practical rationality and logical trains of thought, but also our reaching moral judgment about our moral choices is triggered and utilized as we evolve as consciousnesses.

 

When our intellectually driven good will and articulated application of our consciences to value choices ethically drives our decision-making, then we are attuned to and are an extension of the divine logos and the Creator’s natural law being applied by us to action choices before us in the world. As part of the divine logos that made and runs natural law guiding the universe both, the natural and supernatural worlds, ideas come to us by our rationally intuitive route, or just thinking about options, as logically worked out, defined, labeled concepts full blown into our consciousness.

 

 Thus, good people growing as individuators are rational more than emotional but both are used and should be used to be a good person.

 

A good will of a thinking adult is good and is good reasoning that is morally good. Jordan wants no individualism no freedom, no pride no self no intellect for the masses because he thinks they cannot handle the responsibility of it, and they will no longer lean on him to guide them, and he fears being powerless and ignored.

 

J: “Like zero. So, another way and it’s very important to discriminate intellectual capacity, let’s say or merit, from moral worth.”

 

My response: We may be able to separate intellectual capacity from moral worth a lot, but I believe that the thinking agent—regardless of IQ level--, especially if wise and of good will, is advised to think long and hard among her moral choices, and she can learn to excel at it. If she selects wisely and acts out her selection, there resides her moral worth properly earned, yielding veridical self-pride, pride in one’s thinking, and intellectual decisions made.

 

J: “Because it’s also the case that the intelligent have their temptation. The evil figures of mythology are always stellar intellects gone spectacularly wrong.”

 

My response: The intelligent--and this is everyone who thinks for herself and individuates so she is smart and wise, who avoids giving into temptation most of the time—uses her intellect to be proud, good, and self-interested, and to be moral.

 

 It is the nonindividuator, humble, selfless, feeling-propelled and without pride that is weak-willed, often more bad-willed. She first did not withstand the pack. She cannot withstand her base selfish urges which her consciousness is warning her about. Most evildoers and evil is done by joiners: none are naturally unintelligent even with an IQ of 85. The leaders of evil mobs and gangs may be of stellar intellect but most people willing to follow them are groupists which makes even naturally intelligent persons unintelligent due to social pressure and a love of evil in their midst.

 

J: “That’s why it is always the evil scientist in the modern mythologies, right. All the enemies of the superheroes are evil scientists. They are all evil geniuses. And that’s because general cognitive ability is not only associated with moral per se.”

 

My response: Jordan seems to worry that those that are geniuses will come to worship their own intellects, to become so arrogant and self-deluding that they presume they can bend the fabric of reality by lying and engaging in vice, that karma does not apply to them—only the masses—or as geniuses, they are gods that will rewrite natural law with no ethical limits on what they plan to do, or how they hurt others, or gather power and money unto themselves by any means, for as geniuses they are above natural and supernatural law. God’s rules do not apply to them as trans-humans, as superhumans.

 

My evidence-lacking hunch is that, in reality, geniuses per capita are less evil than dumber people, but all are smart and wise if they wish and do as they should, but sinners or those who refuse to think, learn, grow, keep open-minded and seek truth and objectivity, they choose stupidly and become stupid over time, willfully blind. It is the emotional and anti-intellectual that are associated with immorality per se, and this applies to the masses as well as to geniuses.

 

J: “It’s worse than that in a sense. I think because it is definitely the case that the higher general cognitive ability confers upon, you a tremendous advantage in a complex society. Because you can learn faster, and the differences are not trivial. It’s the biggest singly difference between people is general cognitive ability.”

 

My response: Anyone can learn and learn fast like, when in a complex society, the difference between successful doers and unsuccessful goldbrickers is not general cognitive ability: it is the will and push to learn as much as possible, as fast as possible, and the will to work as hard as possible so the smart individuators are the haves and the dull nonindividuators are stuck in the masses where they were born. The biggest difference, between loving, successful, productive, prosperous, creative individuating winners and self-hating and other-hating, average or poor, minimal producers is that the latter are parasites, poor, derivative, lazy, unambitious, even if not actively revolutionary, nihilist and deconstructive. The thinking egoist presents and inserts his will upon the world, the will to be an individual and the willingness to work hard.

 

The masses with reason, agency, modestly absorbed lifestyle of individualism and some egoist ethics—blended with and hindered by their adopting or being reared in the moral code of altruism and continued accenting group living and conformity--gave us the modern West democracy, capitalism, modern conveniences, and  enormous--almost unimaginable wealth and the wondrous Enlightenment.

 

J: “And it’s an appalling literature to familiarize yourself with to some degree because it does seem to violate the principles on first glance of universal cosmic justice. It’s like why is it fair for some people to be born with an IQ of 85 which barely makes you competent to even be a member of the armed forces, regardless of what role you are in.

 

Or to have an IQ of 145 which opens the doors that say to places like Harvard or investment banking, as a career strategy.”

 

My response: Cosmic justice is that all are born rather smart, some more than others, and if people use their big brains—as Stephen Hicks describes human minds—there are almost no limits to what they can accomplish and achieve if they maverize; the sky is the limit if people would be dream and live their dream and go for it—that is cosmic justice if people choose to live and flourish rather than pack-live and lead their Thoreauian lives of quiet despair and Hofferian discontent.

 

J: “The cards are dealt out in a relatively arbitrary way. Well, that’s a very bitter pill to swallow.”

 

My response: Jordan laments but warns the masses, allegedly but not actually or necessarily immoral, dumb, and inferior, to just accept their fate in life, that they will end up poor or barely scraping by; all they can do is suffer, stay poor, take on all the altruistic suffering and self-sacrificing that they can, and then perhaps heaven is theirs, for there is no material hope for them on earth.

 

Jordan insists that success on earth is granted the gifted and ingenious, and they can even know heaven after death, if they have remained humble and non-Luciferian, if these very smart persons assumed as their telos, a life of moral service to mankind, then they may have paid God back for their intellectual privilege, thus accessing rewards after death in heaven.

 

  Only those with an IQ of 145 will  thrive and only they have the right to try—Eric Hoffer would stingingly refute Jordan by pointing to the rich, free, self-directing, free, practical, happy society-ruling American mass society made by the masses, for the masses, and run (more or less) by the masses, but none of this this does squares with Jordan’s traditional, rather Christian, medieval view that the masses are inferior and must accept their lot and be ruled by the rich, powerful gentry and their clerisy hanger-ons. Jordan’s solution is to return the medieval times—no thank you, Jordan. You do not believe in the masses and nor should they listen to you.

 

J: “But it is also the case that those who are intelligent have the temptation of Lucifer-- essentially, if you think about it mythologically. Because it is very easy to worship your own intellect, and then to worship intellect, per se. And that’s very dangerous thing to do.”

 

My response: Jordan presents a false dilemma: either you humble yourself, prostrate yourself before God, denying your worth, power, agency, right to do things for yourselves, to think and trust your intellect (not worshiping your intellect), or you are filled with supreme but sickening confidence in, reliance upon, and love of your own smart intellect (a delusory stance to assume), worship your own intellect in your vaunted pride and bragging, and you follow Satan, turn evil and will burn.

 

I suggest one worship neither one’s own intellect or God’s intellect, but to have affection and proper pride towards the self—merited pride, and also, real affection and humility before God, to enjoy all of God’s beauty and glory, which includes De’s intellect but not worshiping De’s intellect, which is demonic and blasphemy. God wants humans to have pride and smart intellects, but still to worship God, while not vying against or disrespecting God.

 

J: “To develop that sense of wounded intellectual pride if people are not bowing at your feet, or even the presumption that merely because you’ve been gifted with intelligence, because it’s not something you earned, that means you’re of a stellar moral character.”

 

My response: Obviously, there is no correlation between being smart and being moral, though smarter people might be more logical and rational, and thinking is likely more conducive to being a good person because one knows how to reach wise conclusions about how to live and how to conduct oneself.

 

 Jordan is always too melodramatic though he is accurately describing the wounded pride of those spurned by the masses; these rebuked, would-be-elitists do seek revenge—power, control, and tyranny to get even with the masses.

 

Such wounded, vicious intellectuals are people who are not individualists, who ordinarily are content and at peace with themselves, quietly calm, confident, proud and function well at room temperature. And, as individualists, they seek not power over others, but liberty for all. Individualists do not much care if people think well of them or not, or obey them or not—live and let live is their motto.

 

The intellectuals whom Jordan is referring to are not individualists. They are groupist intellectuals, part of the Party that rules and masses, and these are very dangerous, cruel people if they forcefully grab the power to hurt the masses whom they despise.

 

These joiners, these intellectual elitists, are seriously out to maim the masses, their wounded, Luficerian pride is all packed-geared, all altruistic and selfless. They nurse a special grudge for and hatred against for the self-sufficient American masses who are rightly, instinctively leery of these malcontents. As Eric Hoffer famously emphasizes, the character of these pack intellectuals reveals their evil natures, and these wicked people demonstrate behaviors and traits not those of individualists, or intellectuals, but those of elite joiners running society from its top rungs.

 

J: “I was really shocked in my clinical practice, you know, quite regularly, because people in my practice who were definitely in the lower quintile of intelligence, let’s say, very, very impaired, unable to read, certainly unable to use a computer.

 

They were virtually unemployable regardless of how much effort was poured into that, yet how often they were unbelievably admirable in their in the ability to bear up under the complex and stressful conditions of their life, without being bitter or resentful while still being of service to other people. It was really shocking to me to watch that (Ed says, one can always be grateful and adopt a good attitude, no matter how things have turned out.), and as a reminder that just because you are intelligent, doesn’t mean you are good and that does.

 

And we do in our culture, and the Left is particularly egregious in this regard, I would say, to casually allude to cognitive ability with moral worth, with general cognitive ability.”

 

My response: Moral worth and natural or earned high IQ can be coordinated with individual moral worth only if the agent is grateful, optimistic, positive, loving and seeking wisdom.

 

The less intelligent adults are not naturally more humble and thus better, selfless, more moral person just because they have lower IQs and less talent. Indeed, I would counter argue that those with more intelligence and talent, on average, are naturally more moral than those with less talent and lower IQ, though the difference is not huge, and the difference is of negligible impact if both groups of people decide to live egoistically and maverize, regardless of their IQ and talent.

 

Your moral character is based upon your loving the Good Spirits, loving yourself and then loving others, and when you in action act out loving interchanging with the Good Spirits, with oneself and with others, that is how you become a virtuous and holy agent, and talent and IQ do not factor in that much at all.

 

There is just not a strong causal connection between being brainy and being virtuous, but where the individual is egoistic, and genuinely intellectual and rational, it is likely that moral goodness will follow and permeate the good egoist’s consciousness.

 

J: “You know, if you have a materialist viewpoint, that’s, it’s a very easy thing to do. It’s a hard thing to fight against.”

 

My response: Once again Jordan is astute about discovering a maladaptive human behavior, but his final analysis and solution is mostly inaccurate and disastrous if implemented. His moral solution is the traditional, conventional altruistic answer which promotes other-interest and self-sacrifice, the very evil practices which deplete residual individual self-esteem, and rewards self-loathing and low self-esteem. Remember evil in society is hatred in action and that comes from a phony humility and low self-regard. Jordan’s moral solution will grow evil in the world.

 

It often is so that Leftists and materialists or professors who are secular humanists do worship their own intellects, and their high IQs make them especially susceptible to believing sincerely that because they are smarter than the masses, they are better than the masses, not only intellectually but morally, so the masses should just bow down and allow these educated elitists to run their lives.

 

What Jordan has detected, but mischaracterized and not unpacked and uncovered here, the shocking, fast, universal ache for many perhaps most people to allow a little power and a little status For the insecure joiner, being a bit smarter than the average person is a kind of elevated status, and the urge to chase after this status is most corrupting. He who chases after this petty status would sell his children to acquire a little higher rank on the social pecking order. With slightly altered status as a groupist, these selfless fools allow the modicum of increased personal social power to go right to their heads, to believe that they are above average, and that they now have a right even a duty to direct and straighten out the inferior masses.

 

This global, endemic, sickening proclivity is most alluringand ruins lives, but it does not grow out of individualistic, veridical self-esteem but is meant by insecure, self-loathing power abusers, to give them a little internal or social reassurance that they are no worthless after all, that they are superior to their neighbors, that they must demonstrate this “superiority” over their neighbors by ruling, exploiting, abusing them.

 

This willingness to allow power to go to one’s head grows not out of self-centeredness and self-esteem, nor from overweening pride of the narcissistic Luciferian intellect, but is a compensatory substitution for missing enlightened self-interest and healthy self-regard, by the majority, other-centered, selfless, and group-oriented.

 

J: “Our society does differently award people with high general cognitive ability because our society is very complex and rapidly changing. So, we differentially devote resources to the cognitive skills. And our culture is set up so that’s more and more the case.

 

But then there’s another issue too that I think is totally relevant. You see, the worship of the intellect in and of itself has this danger of pride associated with it. And it’s a very big danger. The way we should be conceptualizing intelligence is the manner in which gifts are portrayed in the gospel accounts, for example.

 

So, one of the things Christ says—two things that are in some ways contradictory. One of them is that ‘to those that have everything, more will be given, and from those that have nothing everything will be taken. So that’s the Matthew Principle.”

 

My response: I have never denied that the Matthew Principle is social reality, but it is only inevitable if people fail to work, maverize, and build prosperity as part of a free market, democratic system. Jordan is on his hobbyhorse again about the brightest being unequally rewarded in our society, so complex and fast changing.

 

He is warning the brightest not to allow being elevated economically, socially, and institutionally, which leads to that accumulated power and special status going to their heads as their worship their intellects, becoming suffused with Luciferian pride, turning away from God and moral goodness.

 

J: “That’s what economists call it. And it is a pointer to the fact regardless of the discipline, resources accrue in the hands of the few. And that’s what Marx observe that capital would accrue in the hands of fewer and fewer people. That’s true. That happens in every society.

 

It doesn’t matter whether it’s a capitalist society or a socialist society by the way, and so he attributed to capitalism which meant he misdiagnosed the problem, because it’s deeper than capitalism.”

 

My response: Jordan as a biological psychologist and research scientist did great work, before he went into axiology and now wants collectivism and altruism for the masses, so dim-witted that if they try to think and develop their talents, they will fail but will become evil because their so attempting is worshiping their individual intellects, so then they will turn evil, anti-God and proud rebels against God in their vaunted Luciferian pride. What nonsense.

 

Still, Jordan is accurate in displaying the Mathew Principle at work for hundreds of millions of years in all life forms that hierarchies and caste systems for human societies seems inevitable—he is correct, it is a natural proclivity in all societies, but it is not inevitable. But the solution is not Marxian revolution, which will only bring about a totalitarian social hell and dystopian of no freedom, pure hierarchical living and unfortunate groupist, low self-esteem, which grows hatred and malevolence in the world.

 

Living in hierarchies is not inevitable but the only cure is rearing up a generation of individuating supercitizens—nothing else works as a lasting or thorough solution.

 

J: “But it is the case that rewards are differentially distributed and that in the higher echelons of the cognitive distribution are more likely to accrue those rewards. But there’s another statement there that is also relevant which is that those that have been given much, much will be required.”

 

My response: I have no problem with God expecting much of those that have been given much, but the rewards are not so much distributed to the talented and smartest based on their genetic gifts: rather they made it to the top, getting there mostly due to the talented and smartest being the most egoistic and industrious, so they earned what they got.

 

If everyone maverizes, everyone will get more of the rewards, and there will still be differences, but the range will not be that great and individuating supercitizens will do just fine, and class society mostly will dissipate and disappear.

 

J: “Like a gift that you misuse turns into your enemy and this is more to justice elements. Like you might be rewarded, like your IQ is stellar. Thank your lucky stars.”

 

My response: Yes, there are altruistic narcissists that crave to rule the pack while remaining members of the pack. This talented and intellectual elite misuse their natural gifts and that make their ability their enemy, but they are damned by leasing to Satan their corrupt wills and unwillingness to serve God as a living angel individuators soldier of God.

 

But this obligation to individuate and serve the Good Spirits is rejected by the wicked,and they are rapidly accruing to themselves the dire consequences for misusing life, life span and talent.

 

That many seek social power rather than work as living angels  is not a justifiable criticism of intellect or that the masses should not and cannot have the ability to reason, be talented or generally excel.

 

Rather it is a reminder for all to live as egoists, and to use our reason to do well, to act well and to individuate, but you are responsible for misusing it and always were, and that is nothing new. People could go to hell thousands of years ago already.

 

J: “Does that make you privileged? It depends on what you do with it. Like if you bore a responsibility that was commensurate with the talent then you’ve paid existentially for your gift. And the classical warning in deep religious texts is that if you misuse a gift that you’ve been granted, it will become an unbearable burden and turn against you.”

 

My response: All are privileged and smart, some more than others, all are talented, some more than others, so what. Get on with it and maverize. Then, you are much less likely to misuse your gifts. You are much more likely to know joy and pleasure as well as duty and responsibility for suffering is part of life, but it is not the whole story, Jordan.

 

 

 

 

                                                            B

 

 

 

 

 

 

Here is an article I copied and pasted in its entirety, off the Internet, on about 6/24/25. My thesis—which does require some qualifying--is that intellect, reasoning and individualism make individuals egoistic and moral, whereas feeling—especially as passion—and denial of the importance of developing one’s intellect and taking proper pride in one’s cogitations and their fruits—make individuals joiners and collectivists, immoral, vain and Luficerian.

 

 

Here is that article:

 

 

                                  NCBI home page

Article 1 (A1 after this): “As a library, NLM provides access to scientific literature. Inclusion in an NLM database does not imply endorsement of, or agreement with, the contents by NLM or the National Institutes of Health.
Learn more: PMC Disclaimer | PMC Copyright Notice

NIHPA Author Manuscripts logo

Annu Rev Psychol

. Author manuscript; available in PMC: 2011 Apr 28.

Published in final edited form as: Annu Rev Psychol. 2007;58:345–372. doi: 10.1146/annurev.psych.56.091103.070145

Moral Emotions and Moral Behavior

June Price Tangney 1,, Jeff Stuewig 1, Debra J Mashek 2

  •  

·  PMCID: PMC3083636  NIHMSID: NIHMS288615  PMID: 16953797

The publisher's version of this article is available at Annu Rev Psychol

Abstract

Moral emotions represent a key element of our human moral apparatus, influencing the link between moral standards and moral behavior. This chapter reviews current theory and research on moral emotions. We first focus on a triad of negatively valenced “self-conscious” emotions—shame, guilt, and embarrassment. As in previous decades, much research remains focused on shame and guilt. We review current thinking on the distinction between shame and guilt, and the relative advantages and disadvantages of these two moral emotions. Several new areas of research are highlighted: research on the domain-specific phenomenon of body shame, styles of coping with shame, psychobiological aspects of shame, the link between childhood abuse and later proneness to shame, and the phenomena of vicarious or “collective” experiences of shame and guilt. In recent years, the concept of moral emotions has been expanded to include several positive emotions—elevation, gratitude, and the sometimes morally relevant experience of pride. Finally, we discuss briefly a morally relevant emotional process—other-oriented empathy.”

My response: Our emotions are an important element of our moral apparatus, influencing the link between moral standards and moral behavior. Emotions are such an important element, but I believe and hope to show that our reasons, intellect, thoughts, logical processes, and rational intuition are the most important element influencing the link between moral standards and moral behavior.

But reasoning is not all good, moral, and individual, and feeling is not all bad, immoral and of the collective. Such a false dichotomy is a lie; it is unworkable, and not how the world works, and we must discover how the world works if we would live better and do better.

My axiom, moderation in most things, applies here. Be individual more than collective. Be moral more than immoral. Seek truth not lies errors and illusions. Think more than feel, but do both, and pursue self-interest more than group-interest, but both are important and play a part. Be proud of your intellect more than not, but only if you have learned to think, are rooted deeply in reality, are individuating. Then your reasoned and felt moral choices will introduce new, uplifting, sensible ideas, and action patterns to the world, for the benefit of all.

 

A1: “Keywords: shame, guilt, pride, elevation, gratitude

OVERVIEW

What confluence of factors foster a moral life lived to the benefit of self and others? This review summarizes current theory and research on moral emotions, offering a framework for thinking about the ways in which morally relevant emotions may moderate the link between moral standards and moral decisions, and ultimately moral behavior.

Living a moral, constructive life is defined by a weighted sum of countless individual, morally relevant behaviors enacted day in and day out (plus an occasional particularly self-defining moment). As imperfect human beings, however, our behavior does not always bear a one-to-one correspondence to our moral standards.”

My response: We must be sensible and reasonable in our expectations: there can never be a one-to-one correspondence between conducted behaviors and actual moral standards. If we come close, that is a great, even adequate effort in divine judger eyes.

A1: “Many potential explanations exist for the discrepancy between behavioral decisions (intentions) and actual behavior in both moral and nonmoral domains. Historically, much social psychological theory and research was devoted to understanding the imperfect link between intentions (e.g., moral decisions) and behavior. Field theory, the very foundation of social psychology, highlights the variability of individual behavior as a function of situational context (Lewin 1943); interpersonal negotiation can undermine the link between intention and behavior (DeVisser & Smith 2004); and diffusion of responsibility can undermine one’s ability to act on deeply held beliefs (see, e.g., Latane & Darley 1968). Ajzen’s (1991) theory of planned behavior offers a well-integrated model of the ways in which attitudes, norms, and perceived control feed into behavioral intentions and subsequent behavior.

As with the link between intentions and behaviors in general, the link between moral intentions and moral behaviors is likewise an important issue. However, owing to space limitations, this chapter focuses on the processes further upstream from intentions: the less widely studied factors that strengthen (or disrupt) linkages between moral standards and moral intentions (which we refer to throughout this article as moral decisions), and thus moral behaviors. In our view, the link between moral standards and moral decisions and/or moral behavior is influenced in important ways by moral emotions.”

My response: The spirit is willing, but the flesh is weak. The gap between moral intentions and moral behavior or practice is made worse because people suffer from low self-esteem—that is they hate themselves more than they love themselves, and an agent in which self-loathing monopolizes her consciousness is an agent who will and must misbehave much of the time, despite her moral code.

A1: “Moral standards represent an individual’s knowledge and internalization of moral norms and conventions. People’s moral standards are dictated in part by universal moral laws, and in part by culturally specific proscriptions. The current review emphasizes cognitive and emotional processes relevant to the more cross-culturally invariant moral standards. Of primary interest are prohibitions against behaviors likely to have negative consequences for the well-being of others and for which there is broad social consensus that such behaviors are “wrong” (e.g., interpersonal violence, criminal behavior, lying, cheating, stealing).”

My response: I enjoy the authors’ emphasis on how the individual internalizes moral norms, so their moral code is partially dictated by universal moral laws and in part by culturally specific proscriptions.

They are recommending that moral emotions upstream of the agent’s intentions, if well developed and self-regulated, could lead the agent to behave better, thus lessening negative behavioral consequences upon others.

Perhaps if moral thinking upstream was added, the agent could behave better, more consistently too in self-care and communal care.

A1: “Naturally, people do, on occasion, lie, cheat, and steal, even though they know such behavior is deemed wrong by moral and societal norms. Individual differences in people’s anticipation of and experience of moral emotions likely play key roles in determining actual moral choices and behavior in real-life contexts.

Moral emotions represent an important but often overlooked element of our human moral apparatus. Moral emotions may be critically important in understanding people’s behavioral adherence (or lack of adherence) to their moral standards. Haidt (2003) defines moral emotions as those “that are linked to the interests or welfare either of society as a whole or at least of persons other than the judge or agent” (p. 276). Moral emotions provide the motivational force—the power and energy— to do good and to avoid doing bad (Kroll & Egan 2004).

In this article, we focus on a triad of morally relevant, negatively valenced “self-conscious” emotions—shame, guilt, and embarrassment. We also consider several positively valenced moral emotions—elevation, gratitude, and the sometimes morally relevant experience of pride. In addition, we discuss briefly a morally relevant emotional process— empathy.”

 

My response: It seems clear that these psychologists regard strong, operative moral emotions as likely to produce ethical adults who are other-centered, compassionate, and empathetic.

A1: “SELF-CONSCIOUS EMOTIONS: ANTICIPATORY AND CONSEQUENTIAL REACTIONS TO THE SELF

Shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride are members of a family of “self-conscious emotions” that are evoked by self-reflection and self-evaluation. This self-evaluation may be implicit or explicit, consciously experienced or transpiring beneath the radar of our awareness. But importantly, the self is the object of these self-conscious emotions.

As the self reflects upon the self, moral self-conscious emotions provide immediate punishment (or reinforcement) of behavior. In effect, shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride function as an emotional moral barometer, providing immediate and salient feedback on our social and moral acceptability. When we sin, transgress, or err, aversive feelings of shame, guilt, or embarrassment are likely to ensue. When we “do the right thing,” positive feelings of pride and self-approval are likely to result.”

My response: It appears that moral reasoning as well as moral emotions can curb behavior in the honestly self-reflective adults who sincerely, actively seeks to be moral in line with her ethical code, feeling guilty when she sins, and self-approving or veridically proud of her actions, when she gets it right.

A1: “Moreover, actual behavior is not necessary for the press of moral emotions to have effect. People can anticipate their likely emotional reactions (e.g., guilt versus pride/self-approval) as they consider behavioral alternatives. Thus, the self-conscious moral emotions can exert a strong influence on moral choice and behavior by providing critical feedback regarding both anticipated behavior (feedback in the form of anticipatory shame, guilt, or pride) and actual behavior (feedback in the form of consequential shame, guilt, or pride). In our view, people’s anticipatory emotional reactions are typically inferred based on history—that is, based on their past consequential emotions in reaction to similar actual behaviors and events.

Thus far, we have been discussing situation-specific experiences of consequential and anticipatory feelings of shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride. In the realm of moral emotions, researchers are also interested in dispositional tendencies to experience these self-conscious emotions (e.g., shame-proneness, guilt-proneness). An emotion disposition is defined as the propensity to experience that emotion across a range of situations (Tangney 1990). From this perspective, shame-prone individuals would be more susceptible to both anticipatory and consequential experiences of shame, relative to their less shame-prone peers. That is, a shame-prone person would be inclined to anticipate shame in response to a range of potential behaviors and outcomes. In turn, such an individual also would be inclined to experience shame as a consequence of actual failures and transgressions.

Shame and Guilt

The vast majority of research on moral emotions has focused on two negatively valanced, self-conscious emotions—shame and guilt. Many individuals, including clinicians, researchers, and lay people, use the terms “shame” and “guilt” synonymously. Nonetheless, a number of attempts have been made to differentiate between shame and guilt over the years.

What’s the difference between shame and guilt?

Attempts to differentiate between shame and guilt fall into three categories: (a) a distinction based on types of eliciting events, (b) a distinction based on the public versus private nature of the transgression, and (c) a distinction based on the degree to which the person construes the emotion-eliciting event as a failure of self or behavior.

Research indicates that type of event has surprisingly little to do with the distinction between shame and guilt. Analyses of personal shame and guilt experiences provided by children and adults revealed few, if any, “classic” shame-inducing or guilt-inducing situations (Keltner&Buswell 1996, Tangney 1992, Tangney et al. 1994, Tracy & Robins 2006). Most types of events (e.g., lying, cheating, stealing, failing to help another, disobeying parents) are cited by some people in connection with feelings of shame and by other people in connection with guilt. Some researchers claim that shame is evoked by a broader range of situations including both moral and nonmoral failures and transgressions, whereas guilt is more specifically linked to transgressions in the moral realm (Ferguson et al. 1991, Sabini & Silver 1997, Smith et al. 2002). In our view (Tangney et al. 2006b), like its sibling guilt, shame qualifies as a predominantly moral emotion, once one moves beyond narrowly conceptualizing the domain of morality in terms of the ethic of autonomy (Shweder et al. 1997). Of the “Big Three” ethics of morality—autonomy, community, and divinity (Shweder et al. 1997)—shame may be more closely tied to violations of the ethics of community (e.g., violations of the social order) and divinity (e.g., actions that remind us of our animal nature), but violations of particular ethics do not bear a one-to-one correspondence to particular situations or events. As demonstrated by Shweder et al. (1997), most failures and transgressions are experienced as relevant to a mix of moral ethics. In short, from this broader cultural perspective, shame and guilt are emotions each primarily evoked by moral lapses.

Another frequently cited distinction between shame and guilt focuses on the public versus private nature of transgressions (e.g., Benedict 1946). From this perspective, shame is viewed as the more “public” emotion arising from public exposure and disapproval of some shortcoming or transgression. Guilt, on the other hand, is conceived as a more “private” experience arising from self-generated pangs of conscience. As it turns out, empirical research has failed to support this public/private distinction in terms of the actual structure of the emotion-eliciting situation (Tangney et al. 1994, 1996a). For example, a systematic analysis of the social context of personal shame- and guilt-eliciting events described by several hundred children and adults (Tangney et al. 1994) indicated that shame and guilt are equally likely to be experienced in the presence of others. Solitary shame experiences were about as common as solitary guilt experiences. Even more to the point, the frequency with which others were aware of the respondents’ behavior did not vary as a function of shame and guilt, in direct contradiction to the public/private distinction. Similarly, in a study of personal emotion narratives, Tracy & Robins (2006) found that, relative to guilt, shame was elicited somewhat more frequently by achievement events and personal events, which are each more private than relational and familial events.”

 

My response: Again, rational morals and emotional morals could both trigger feelings of guilt and shame if one sins. My sense of it is that veridical private guilt should motivate people of good will and strong conscience not to go and sin no more or less so.

Being shamed is a social method of behavior modification, so therefore less useful and less lasting. When remorse is individual and feeling guilty, it is self-oriented, so lasting reform is possible. When remorse is the emotion experienced by the targeted sinner being shamed,  this other-oriented suffering will not likely lead the sinner to reform.

A1: “Where does the notion that shame is a more public emotion come from? Although shame- and guilt-inducing situations are equally public (in terms of the likelihood that others are present and aware of the failure or transgression) and equally likely to involve interpersonal concerns, there appear to be systematic differences in the nature of those interpersonal concerns. Tangney et al. (1994) found that when describing shame-inducing situations, respondents expressed more concern with others’ evaluations of the self. In contrast, when describing guilt experiences, respondents were more concerned with their effect on others. This difference in “egocentric” versus “other-oriented” concerns isn’t surprising given that shame involves a focus on the self, whereas guilt relates to a specific behavior. A shamed person who is focusing on negative self-evaluations would naturally be drawn to a concern over others’ evaluations. It’s a short leap from thinking what a horrible person one is to thinking about how one might be evaluated by others. On the other hand, a person experiencing guilt is already relatively “decentered”—focusing on a negative behavior somewhat separate from the self. In focusing on a bad behavior, rather than a bad self, a person in the middle of a guilt experience is more likely to recognize (and have concerns about) the effects of that behavior on others rather than on others’ evaluations. Several subsequent studies (Smith et al. 2002) provide ample evidence that shame is associated with such concerns. For example, participants primed to focus on public exposure of a moral transgression attributed equivalent levels of shame and guilt to story protagonists, but when the public versus private dimension was not highlighted, participants attributed less shame (guilt was uniformly high across conditions). However, taken together, Smith et al.’s findings are consistent with the notion that people focus on others’ evaluations because they are feeling shame, not vice versa. When participants were asked to think of a situation in which they had felt bad because an inferior aspect of themselves “was revealed or publicly exposed to another person or to other people” (p. 154; emphasis added), the majority spontaneously described the resulting feeling as one of embarrassment—only 6.7% identified the feeling as shame (twice as many identified the feeling as guilt). Similarly, in the moral condition (feeling bad because “something wrong” that they did was exposed), the modal emotion term was embarrassment—three times more common than shame (which was no more frequent than guilt). In short, when experiencing shame, people may feel more exposed—more aware of others’ disapproval—but the reality is that situations causing both shame and guilt are typically social in nature. More often than not, our failures and transgressions do not escape the notice of others.

The currently most dominant basis for distinguishing between shame and guilt—focus on self versus behavior—was first proposed by Helen Block Lewis (1971) and more recently elaborated by Tracy & Robins’s (2004a) appraisal-based model of self-conscious emotions. According to Lewis (1971), shame involves a negative evaluation of the global self; guilt involves a negative evaluation of a specific behavior. Although this distinction may, at first glance, appear rather subtle, empirical research supports that this differential emphasis on self (“I did that horrible thing”) versus behavior (“I did that horrible thing”) sets the stage for very different emotional experiences and very different patterns of motivations and subsequent behavior.

Both shame and guilt are negative emotions and as such, both can cause intrapsychic pain. Nonetheless, shame is considered the more painful emotion because one’s core self—not simply one’s behavior—is at stake. Feelings of shame are typically accompanied by a sense of shrinking or of “being small” and by a sense of worthlessness and power-lessness. Shamed people also feel exposed. Although shame does not necessarily involve an actual observing audience present to witness one’s shortcomings, there is often the imagery of how one’s defective self would appear to others. Lewis (1971) described a split in self-functioning in which the self is both agent and object of observation and disapproval. Guilt, on the other hand, is typically a less devastating, less painful experience because the object of condemnation is a specific behavior, not the entire self. Rather than needing to defend the exposed core of one’s identity, people in the throes of guilt are drawn to consider their behavior and its consequences. This focus leads to tension, remorse, and regret over the “bad thing done.”

Empirical support for Lewis’s (1971) distinction between shame and guilt comes from a range of experimental and correlational studies employing a range of methods including qualitative case study analyses, content analyses of shame and guilt narratives, participants’ quantitative ratings of personal shame and guilt experiences, analyses of attributions associated with shame and guilt, and analyses of participants’ counterfactual thinking (for a review, see Tangney & Dearing 2002). Most recently, for example, Tracy & Robins (2006) employed both experimental and correlational methods showing that internal, stable, uncontrollable attributions for failure were positively related to shame, whereas internal, unstable, controllable attributions for failure were positively related to guilt.

Shame and guilt are not equally “moral” emotions

One of the consistent themes emerging from empirical research is that shame and guilt are not equally “moral” emotions. On balance, guilt appears to be the more adaptive emotion, benefiting individuals and their relationships in a variety of ways (Baumeister et al. 1994, 1995a,b; Tangney 1991, 1995a,b), but there is growing evidence that shame is a moral emotion that can easily go awry (Tangney 1991, 1995a,b; Tangney et al. 1996b).”

 

My response: I am no psychologist and no social scientist, but these reasonable researchers do seem to be onto something, that feeling ashamed is a social phenomenon, where morality is an individual phenomenon, so if one concentrates on feeling guilt over one’s bad behavior, and seeks to atone and do better, this private and personal approach might more closely elicit via an active conscience, better behavior because the individual chooses to act better, so that he can again approve of himself only when he mostly meets his ethical standard which he has imposed upon himself.

A1: “In this section, we summarize research in five areas that illustrates the adaptive functions of guilt, in contrast to the hidden costs of shame. Specifically, we focus on the differential relationship of shame and guilt to motivation (hiding versus amending), other-oriented empathy, anger and aggression, psychological symptoms, and deterrence of transgression and other risky, socially undesirable behavior.

Hiding versus amending

Research consistently shows that shame and guilt lead to contrasting motivations or “action tendencies” (Ketelaar & Au 2003, Lewis 1971, Lindsay-Hartz 1984, Tangney 1993, Tangney et al. 1996a, Wallbott & Scherer 1995, Wicker et al. 1983). On the one hand, shame corresponds with attempts to deny, hide, or escape the shame-inducing situation. Physiological research has linked the shame experience with elevated levels of proinflammatory cytokine and cortisol (Dickerson et al. 2004a), which can trigger postural signs of deference and self-concealment (see New Directions in Research on Shame and Guilt: Physiological Correlates of Shame). Guilt, on the other hand, corresponds with reparative actions including confessions, apologies, and undoing the consequences of the behavior. On the whole, empirical evidence evaluating the action tendencies of people experiencing shame and guilt suggests that guilt promotes constructive, proactive pursuits, whereas shame promotes defensiveness, interpersonal separation, and distance.

Other-oriented empathy versus self-oriented distress

Second, shame and guilt are differentially related to empathy. Specifically, guilt goes hand in hand with other-oriented empathy. Feelings of shame, in contrast, apparently disrupt individuals’ ability to form empathic connections with others. This differential relationship of shame and guilt to empathy is apparent both at the level of emotion disposition and at the level of emotional state. Research on emotional dispositions (Joireman 2004; Leith & Baumeister 1998; Tangney 1991, 1995b; Tangney & Dearing 2002) demonstrates that guilt-proneness consistently correlates with measures of perspective-taking and empathic concern. In contrast, shame-proneness is (depending on assessment method) negatively or negligibly correlated with other-oriented empathy and positively linked with the tendency to focus egocentrically on one’s own distress. Similar findings arise in research on emotional states—feelings of shame and guilt “in the moment.” In describing personal experiences of guilt, people convey greater empathy for others than when describing shame experiences (Leith & Baumeister 1998, Tangney et al. 1994). Marschall (1996) found that people induced to feel shame subsequently reported less empathy for a disabled student, especially among low-shame-prone individuals.”

 

My response: The researchers suggest feeling guilty renders one more sympathetic to others whom one has transgressed against, while feeling shame is more superficial and egocentric so that one really does not become more moral, a group-interested state of moral being.

As an egoist, I flip this around: if feeling guilty about one sins is how one feels, that is a personal feeling which is ego-centered—we straighten out ourselves first, and then we can treat others better. It is unlike feeling shame, a group-status feeling of being socially downgraded and other-centric, so then one does not reform as deep and as well, because the self is not really upset enough as an individual to take action for the better.

A1: “”Why might shame, but not guilt, interfere with other-oriented empathy? Shame’s inherently egocentric focus on the “bad self” (as opposed to the bad behavior) derails the empathic process. Individuals in the throes of shame turn tightly inward, and are thus less able to focus cognitive and emotional resources on the harmed other (Tangney et al. 1994). In contrast, people experiencing guilt are specifically focused on the bad behavior, which in turn highlights the negative consequences experienced by others, thereby fostering an empathic response and motivating people to “right the wrong.”

Constructive versus destructive reactions to anger

Third, research indicates a robust link between shame and anger, again observed at both the dispositional and state levels. In her earlier clinical case studies, Helen Block Lewis (1971) observed the peculiar dynamic between shame and anger (or humiliated fury), noting that clients’ feelings of shame often preceded expressions of anger and hostility in the therapy room. More recent empirical research has supported her claim. Across individuals of all ages, proneness to shame is positively correlated with anger, hostility, and the propensity to blame factors beyond the self for one’s misfortunes (Andrews et al. 2000, Bennett, et al. 2005, Harper & Arias 2004, Paulhus et al. 2004, Tangney & Dearing 2002).

In fact, compared with those who are not shame-prone, shame-prone individuals are more likely to engage in externalization of blame, experience intense anger, and express that anger in destructive ways, including direct physical, verbal, and symbolic aggression, indirect aggression (e.g., harming something important to the target, talking behind the target’s back), all manner of displaced aggression, self-directed aggression, and anger held in (a ruminative unexpressed anger). Finally, shame-prone individuals report awareness that their anger typically results in negative long-term consequences for both themselves and for their relationships with others.

Guilt-proneness, in contrast, is consistently associated with a more constructive constellation of emotions, cognitions, and behaviors. For example, proneness to “shame-free” guilt is positively correlated with constructive intentions in the wake of wrongdoing and consequent constructive behaviors (e.g., nonhostile discussion, direct corrective action). Compared with their nonguilt-prone peers, guilt-prone individuals are less likely to engage in direct, indirect, and displaced aggression when angered. And they report positive long-term consequences to their anger (Tangney et al. 1996a). Consistent with these findings, Harper et al. (2005) recently evaluated the link between shame-proneness and perpetration of psychological abuse in the dating relationships by heterosexual college men. Shame proneness was significantly correlated with perpetration of psychological abuse, and men’s anger mediated this relationship.

Shame and anger have been similarly linked at the situational level, too (Tangney et al. 1996a, Wicker et al. 1983). For example, in a study of anger episodes among romantically involved couples, shamed partners were significantly more angry, more likely to engage in aggressive behavior, and less likely to elicit conciliatory behavior from their perpetrating significant other (Tangney 1995b). Taken together, the results provide a powerful empirical example of the shame-rage spiral described by Lewis (1971) and Scheff (1987), with (a) partner shame leading to feelings of rage, (b) and destructive retaliation, (c) which then sets into motion anger and resentment in the perpetrator, (d ) as well as expressions of blame and retaliation in kind, (e) which is then likely to further shame the initially shamed partner, and so forth—without any constructive resolution in sight.

Recently, Stuewig et al. (2006) examined mediators of the link between moral emotions and aggression in four samples. We theorized that negative feelings associated with shame lead to externalization of blame, which in turn leads shame-prone people to react aggressively. Guilt, on the other hand, should facilitate empathic processes, thus reducing outward directed aggression. As anticipated, we found that across all samples, externalization of blame mediated the relationship between shame-proneness and both verbal and physical aggression. Guilt-proneness, on the other hand, continued to show a direct inverse relationship to aggression in three of the four samples. In addition, the link between guilt and low aggression was partially mediated through other-oriented empathy and a propensity to take responsibility.

In short, shame and anger go hand in hand. Desperate to escape painful feelings of shame, shamed individuals are apt to turn the tables defensively, externalizing blame and anger outward onto a convenient scapegoat. Blaming others may help individuals regain some sense of control and superiority in their life, but the long-term costs are often steep. Friends, coworkers, and loved ones are apt to become alienated by an interpersonal style characterized by irrational bursts of anger.”

My response: When shamed individuals scapegoat onto others, it is because they are other-centric not ego-centric as the researchers have concluded.

A1: “Psychological symptoms

When considering the domain of social behavior and interpersonal adjustment, empirical research suggests that guilt, on balance, is the more moral or adaptive emotion. Guilt appears to motivate reparative action, foster other-oriented empathy, and promote constructive strategies for coping with anger. But are there intrapersonal or intrapsychic costs for those individuals who are prone to experience guilt? Does guilt-proneness lead to anxiety, depression, and/or a loss of self-esteem? Conversely, is shame perhaps less problematic for intrapersonal as opposed to interpersonal adjustment?

The answer is clear in the case of shame. Research over the past two decades consistently indicates that proneness to shame is related to a wide variety of psychological symptoms. These run the gamut from low self-esteem, depression, and anxiety to eating disorder symptoms, posttraumatic stress disorder (PTSD), and suicidal ideation (Andrews et al. 2000, Ashby et al. 2006, Brewin et al. 2000, Crossley & Rockett 2005, Feiring & Taska 2005, Feiring et al. 2002, Ferguson et al. 2000, Ghatavi et al. 2002, Harper & Arias 2004, Henderson & Zimbardo 2001, Leskela et al. 2002, Mills 2003, Murray et al. 2000, Orsillo et al. 1996, Sanftner et al. 1995, Stuewig & McCloskey 2005; see also review in Tangney & Dearing 2002). The negative psychological implications of shame are evident across measurement methods, diverse age groups, and populations. Both the clinical literature and empirical research agree that people who frequently experience feelings of shame about the self are correspondingly more vulnerable to a range of psychological problems.

Although the traditional view is that guilt plays a significant role in psychological symptoms, the empirical findings have been more equivocal. Clinical theory and case studies make frequent reference to a maladaptive guilt characterized by chronic self-blame and obsessive rumination over one’s transgressions (Blatt 1974, Ellis 1962, Freud 1924/1961, Hartmann & Loewenstein 1962, Rodin et al. 1984, Weiss 1993). Recently, however, theorists and researchers have emphasized the adaptive functions of guilt, particularly for interpersonal behavior (Baumeister et al. 1994, 1995a; Hoffman 1982; Tangney 1991, 1994, 1995b; Tangney et al. 1992; Tangney & Dearing 2002).

In an effort to reconcile these perspectives, Tangney (1996) argued that earlier work failed to take into account the distinction between guilt and shame. Once one conceptualizes guilt as a negative emotion in response to a specific failure or transgression, there’s no compelling reason to expect guilt to be associated with poor psychological adjustment. Instead, guilt is most likely to be maladaptive when it becomes fused with shame. The advantages of guilt are lost when a person’s guilt experience (“Oh, look at what a horrible thing I have done”) is magnified and generalized to the self (“ and aren’t I a horrible person”). Ultimately, it’s the shame component of this sequence—not the guilt component— that poses the problem, as the person becomes saddled with feelings of contempt and disgust for a bad, defective self.”

 

My response: I do think the researchers are correct that we should teach sinners to feel guilty about bad behavior, more than shame themselves as bad persons. If we change the behavior, we will be able to feel veridical self-esteem meritoriously increase and that increases self-love, and self-esteem and when one loves the self, then one will love other smore, and act better towards the self and others, lessening the need to feel shame or guilt.

A1: “Moreover, such painful feelings of shame are difficult to resolve. Shame—and, shame-fused guilt—offers little opportunity for redemption. It is a daunting challenge to transform a self that is defective at its core. Thus, guilt with an overlay of shame is most likely the source of the painful self-castigation and rumination so often described in the clinical literature. In contrast, there are typically a multitude of paths to redemption in the case of uncomplicated guilt focused on a specific behavior. A person (a) often has the option of changing the objectionable behavior; (b) or even better yet, has an opportunity to repair the negative consequences; (c) or at the very least, can extend a heartfelt apology. And when it is not possible to make these external amends, one can resolve to do better in the future.

Consistent with this conceptual analysis, empirical studies that fail to take into account the distinction between shame and guilt, or that employ adjective checklist-type (and other globally worded) measures that are ill-suited to distinguish between shame and guilt, report that guilt-proneness is associated with psychological symptoms (Boye et al. 2002, Fontana & Rosenbeck 2004, Ghatavi et al. 2002, Harder 1995, Jones & Kugler 1993, Meehan et al. 1996). For example, using the Interpersonal Guilt Questionnaire (O’Connor et al. 1997), Berghold & Locke (2002) found that solely the “self-hate” guilt scale differentiated between a control group and adolescents diagnosed with anorexia nervosa. (The authors concluded that, in fact, shame—not guilt—is more important to a clinical understanding of this eating disorder.)

On the other hand, measures sensitive to Lewis’s (1971) distinction between shame about the self versus guilt about a specific behavior (e.g., scenario-based methods assessing shame and guilt with respect to specific situations) show that the propensity to experience “shame-free” guilt is essentially unrelated to psychological symptoms. Numerous independent studies converge: guilt-prone children, adolescents, and adults are not at increased risk for depression, anxiety, low self-esteem, etc. (Gramzow & Tangney 1992; Leskela et al. 2002; McLaughlin 2002; Quiles & Bybee 1997; Schaefer 2000; Stuewig & McCloskey 2005; Tangney 1994; Tangney & Dearing 2002; Tangney et al. 1991, 1992, 1995).

It is worth noting, however, that in most scenario-based measures of shame and guilt (including the Test of Self-Conscious Affect, or TOSCA), the majority of situations are relatively ambiguous regarding responsibility or culpability. For the negatively valenced (but not positively valenced) situations, respondents are asked to imagine events in which they clearly failed or transgressed in some way. Problems are likely to arise when people developed an exaggerated or distorted sense of responsibility for events beyond their control or for which they have no personal involvement (Ferguson et al. 2000, Tangney & Dearing 2002, Zahn-Waxler & Robinson 1995). Survivor guilt is a prime example of such a problematic guilt response that has been consistently linked to psychological maladjustment (Kubany et al. 1995, 2004; O’Connor et al. 2002). In an experimental study of elementary school–aged children, Ferguson et al. (2000) varied the degree to which situations in a scenario-based measure were ambiguous with respect to responsibility. They found a positive relationship between internalizing symptoms (e.g., depression) and proneness to guilt specifically in situations where responsibility was ambiguous.

In short, the benefits of guilt are evident when people acknowledge their failures and transgressions and take appropriate responsibility for their misdeeds. In such situations, the interpersonal benefits of guilt do not appear to come at a cost to the individual. The propensity to experience “shame-free” guilt in response to clear transgressions is generally unrelated to psychological problems, whereas shame is consistently associated with maladaptive processes and outcomes at multiple levels.”

 

My response: I agree that feeling shame over one’s transgression will lead to further corruption in the self and psychological dysfunction, where as guilt linked to bad behaviors specifically are useful for the self to shape up, behave and heal.

A1: “Linking moral emotions to risky, illegal, and otherwise inadvisable behavior

Because shame and guilt are painful emotions, it is often assumed that they motivate individuals to avoid doing wrong. From this perspective, anticipated shame and guilt should decrease the likelihood of transgression and impropriety. But what exactly do the data show?

Empirical studies of diverse samples, employing a range of measures, clearly indicate that guilt-proneness is inversely related to antisocial and risky behavior. In a study of college undergraduates (Tangney 1994), guilt-proneness was associated with endorsing such items as “I would not steal something I needed, even if I were sure I could get away with it.” Similarly, Tibbetts (2003) found that college students’ guilt-proneness was inversely related to self-reported criminal activity. Among adolescents, proneness to shame-free guilt has been negatively correlated with delinquency (Merisca & Bybee 1994, Stuewig & McCloskey 2005; although Ferguson et al.1999 found a negative relationship between guilt-proneness and externalizing symptoms among boys, the opposite was true for girls). The moral emotions appear to be well established by middle childhood and have implications for moral behavior for years to come (Tangney & Dearing 2002). Children prone to shame-free guilt in the fifth grade were, in adolescence, less likely to be arrested, convicted, and incarcerated. They were more likely to practice safe sex, and they were less likely to abuse drugs. Importantly, these findings held when controlling for family income and mothers’ education. Guilt-prone college students, too, are less likely to abuse drugs and alcohol (Dearing et al. 2005). Even among adults already at high risk, guilt-proneness appears to serve a protective function. In a longitudinal study of jail inmates, guilt-proneness assessed shortly after incarceration negatively predicted recidivism and substance abuse during the first year post-release (Tangney et al. 2006).

The pattern of results for shame is quite different, with virtually no evidence supporting the presumed adaptive nature of shame. In studies of children, adolescents, college students, and jail inmates, shame does not appear to serve the same inhibitory functions as guilt (Dearing et al. 2005, Stuewig & McCloskey 2005, Tangney et al. 1996b). To the contrary, research suggests that shame may even make things worse. In a study of children, Ferguson et al. (1999) found that shame-proneness was positively correlated with externalizing symptoms on the Child Behavior Checklist. In a sample of college students, Tibbetts (1997) found a positive relationship between shame-proneness and intentions toward illegal behavior. Shame-proneness assessed in the fifth grade predicted later risky driving behavior, earlier initiation of drug and alcohol use, and a lower likelihood of practicing safe sex (Tangney & Dearing 2002). Similarly, proneness to problematic feelings of shame has been positively linked to substance use and abuse in adulthood (Dearing et al. 2005, Meehan et al. 1996, O’Connor et al. 1994, Tangney et al. 2006).

The differential link of shame and guilt to moral behavior may not generalize across all populations with respect to all behaviors. Harris (2003) assessed event-specific experiences of shame and guilt among drunk-driving offenders following their appearance in court or at a restorative justice conference. In contrast to most extant studies, Harris found no evidence that shame and guilt form distinct factors. It’s important to note that this study focused on a unique,homogeneous sample (convicted drunk drivers, many of whom have substance abuse problems) and a single type of transgression. Harris’s findings raise the intriguing possibility that individuals with substance abuse problems may not have well-differentiated experiences of shame and guilt. Alternatively, guilt and its attendant empathic focus on the harmed other may be less relevant to transgressions, such as drunk driving, that typically do not result in objective physical harm to others. (That is, the magnitude of consequences of an automobile accident is potentially huge, whereas the probability of its occurrence on any given occasion is rather small. Most drunk-driving offenders are arrested for erratic driving, not at the scene of an accident involving actual harm to another person.)

In sum, empirical results converge, indicating that guilt but not shame is most effective in motivating people to choose the moral paths in life. The capacity for guilt is more apt to foster a lifelong pattern of moral behavior, motivating individuals to accept responsibility and take reparative action in the wake of the occasional failure or transgression. In contrast, research has linked shame with a range of illegal, risky, or otherwise problematic behaviors. Thus, when considering the welfare of the individual, his or her close relationships, or society, feelings of guilt represent the moral emotion of choice.

New directions in research on shame and guilt

Context- or domain-specific shame and guilt

Some clinicians have lamented the research literature’s heavy focus on dispositional shame (Leeming & Boyle 2002). Andrews (1998) notes that at least three different conceptualizations of the high-shame individual are implicit in the range of current dispositional measures of shame. Some researchers conceptualize shame-proneness as the propensity to experience shame across a range of situations (operationalized by scenario-based measures such as the TOSCA-3). Others conceptualize high-shame individuals as those who frequently or continuously experience global shame, an affect not necessarily connected to particular events (operationalized by global adjective checklists, such as the PFQ-2, and by the Internalized Shame Scale). A third and more recent conceptualization of “high shame” is explicitly domain specific— individuals who are chronically shamed about particular circumscribed behaviors or personal characteristics (e.g., physical appearance, level of education, race/ethnicity, and stuttering).

A number of researchers have developed measures to assess shame and guilt with respect to specific domains. For example, researchers concerned with the psychology of eating disorders and those exploring hypotheses drawn from the Objectification Theory of Frederickson & Roberts (1997) have assessed feelings of shame specifically in reference to one’s body. “Body shame” has been consistently associated with self-objectification and eating disorder symptoms (Hallsworth et al. 2005). Andrews (1995, 1998) has examined the link between childhood abuse and body shame (see below).

Regarding guilt, researchers have begun to examine the nature and implications of domain-specific feelings of guilt associated with trauma. Trauma-related guilt cognitions, such as false beliefs about responsibility or pre-outcome knowledge, are reliably associated with symptoms of depression among diverse samples of trauma survivors (Blacher 2000; Kubany et al. 1995, 2004; Lee et al. 2001). Moreover, cognitive processing therapy and prolonged exposure interventions appear to be effective at reducing trauma-related guilt cognitions (Nishith et al. 2005, Resick et al. 2002).

Styles of coping with the shame (and guilt) experience

Most theory and research on shame and guilt has focused on the events that lead up to these emotional experiences, the phenomenology of these emotions, or the consequences of these emotions for motivation and behavior. Less attention has been directed toward how people cope with aversive feelings of shame and guilt. Drawing on Nathanson’s (1992) Compass of Shame theory, Elison et al. (2006a) developed a measure of individual differences in coping with shame. The Compass of Shame Scale (COSS-4) consists of four 10-item scales representing the poles of Nathanson’s Compass of Shame plus a fifth assessing adaptive responses. More specifically:

“Attack Self” assesses inward-directed anger and blame (e.g., self-disgust)

“Withdrawal” assesses the tendency to hide or withdraw when shamed (e.g., avoid others)

“Avoidance” assesses disavowal and emotional distancing or minimization (e.g., minimizing the importance of a failing grade)

“Attack Other” assesses outward-directed anger and blame (e.g., blaming someone else for the failure or transgression)

“Adaptive” assesses acknowledgment of shame and motivation to apologize and/or make amends

Some clear parallels exist between the scales of the COSS-4 and the scales of the TOSCA. Attack Self and Withdrawal bear a close resemblance to the two types of items that comprise the TOSCA Shame scale— negative self-appraisals and avoidance. The Adaptive Responses scale bears a close resemblance to the TOSCA Guilt scale. Attack Other bears considerable resemblance to the TOSCA Externalization of Blame scale. And Avoidance resembles the TOSCA Detachment scale (although the TOSCA Detachment scale appears less internally consistent than the COSS-4 Avoidance scale). The use of different terms to describe similar types of response most likely reflects differences in theoretical formulation. Nathanson (1992) draws on modern psychoanalytic theory, Tomkin’s (1963) emotion theory, and associated attachment theory. The TOSCA measures were informed by social-cognitive theories of emotion, with much influence from Lewis (1971). As one might expect, of the four scales of the COSS-4, the Withdrawal and Attack Self scales are most highly correlated with shame, as well as measures of more general psychological adjustment (Elison et al. 2006a,b).

In a sample of undergraduates, Campbell & Elison (2005) found that both subscales of the Self-Report Psychopathy Scale (SRPS) were negatively related to the guilt-like Adaptive Response to Shame scale and positively related to Attack Others and Avoidance scales. The SRPS subscale assessing antisocial lifestyle paralleling Hare’s (1991) Factor 2 on the Psychopathy Checklist-Revised was positively correlated with Attack Self and Withdrawal scales—scales that assess shame much as defined by Lewis (1971) and Tangney (1996). But the Primary Psychopathy subscale, assessing psychopathic personality features akin to Hare’s (1991) Factor 1, was negatively or negligibly related to shame per se—the Attack Self and Withdrawal scales. Future research examining how correlates of the COSS-4 parallel or differ from the TOSCA is needed.

Psychobiological correlates of shame

Researchers have recently begun to evaluate psychobiological markers of shame, examining biological responses to laboratory manipulations designed to threaten the social self (Dickerson et al. 2004b, Gruenewald et al. 2004; see Dickerson et al. 2004a for a review). Dickerson et al. found that participants who wrote about incidents wrought with self-blame, in contrast to participants who wrote about daily activities, evidenced increased levels of self-reported shame (and guilt) from pretest to post-test. More importantly, these same participants evidenced increased proinflammatory cytokine activity from pretest to post-test, and this response was significantly predicted by increases in self-reported shame. Consistent with theory differentiating shame and guilt, shame uniquely predicted this immune-related response; changes in neither guilt nor general negative affect significantly predicted changes in the cytokine response. Recent applied research is equally suggestive: Among people with HIV, persistent feelings of shame predicted t-cell decline, an indicator of compromised immune function (Weitzman et al. 2004).

Gruenewald et al. (2004) examined cortisol responses of individuals performing stressful speaking and arithmetic tasks with and without an audience. Individuals in the social evaluation condition reported more shame (and lower self-esteem) than did individuals in the nonevaluative condition. Moreover, those individuals in this shame-eliciting condition also evidenced significant increases in cortisol levels. Similarly, among children, nonverbal expressions of shame and embarrassment during laboratory tasks were associated with greater cortisol changes during the session, relative to other nonverbal behavioral styles (Lewis & Ramsay 2002).

Considering these patterns of immunoresponse in toto, Dickerson et al. (2004a) note, “ shame may be experienced particularly in conditions characterized by negative social evaluation and rejection. The cortisol and proinflammatory cytokine systems also appear to be responsive to social-evaluative threat. While tentative, there is support for the notion that the activation of these systems under the very specific condition of threat to the social self may hinge on the experience of shame and related emotions” (p. 1205).

Cardiovascular reactivity seems likewise associated with experiences of shame. For example, in addition to evaluating cortisol response, Gruenewald et al. (2004) also evaluated heart rate and blood pressure changes in response to the stressful speaking and arithmetic tasks. Although heart rate and systolic blood pressure increased in both the social evaluative and nonevaluative conditions, the response was somewhat more marked in the social evaluative condition. Extending this work with a clever laboratory manipulation of experienced emotions, Herrald & Tomaka (2002) evaluated cardiovascular reactivity in the wake of pride, shame, and anger. They found that the negatively valenced emotions of shame and anger resulted in higher levels of cardiovascular reactivity than pride; importantly, participants in the shame condition showed higher peripheral resistance (associated with hypertension) and participants in the anger condition showed higher cardiac contractility (associated with coronary disease).

In sum, there seems to be distinct physiological correlates corresponding to the experience of shame. Such physiological markers may prove to be useful as a measurement tool in future research on situation-specific states of shame.

Childhood abuse and the propensity to experience shame

Clinicians have long reported that victims of abuse or trauma are often haunted by feelings of shame. This may especially be true in cases of child maltreatment because of its secretive and hidden nature (Deblinger & Runyon 2005). The experience of abuse at a young age may instigate and reinforce shame-inducing thoughts (Andrews 1998). Also, severely punitive parenting practices may engender in children feelings of helplessness and self-blame, which may then lead to a globalized sense of shame. Although child maltreatment in its different forms (physical abuse, sexual abuse, neglect, harsh parenting) has long been theorized to engender a vulnerability to shame, systematic empirical research has been conducted only recently.

A number of studies have found a relationship between childhood physical and sexual abuse and specific forms of shame, including body shame (Andrews 1995, Andrews & Hunter 1997) and shame about a traumatic event (Andrews et al. 2000). In addition, Murray & Waller (2002) found a relationship between unwanted sexual experience of any sort and internalized shame. Although Hoglund & Nicholas (1995) reported no relationship between a history of physical abuse and shame-proneness, they did find a link between shame-proneness and history of emotional abuse. In this same vein, Gilbert et al. (1996) found that put-downs and shaming practices by parents were associated with adult children’s shame-proneness. Each of these studies, however, was based on retrospective reports of maltreatment and parenting practices, which have known weaknesses (Widom et al. 2004).

Nonetheless, when considering studies using prospective or observational designs, the results for nonsexual abuse and shame are similar. Bennett et al. (2005) report an association between physical abuse and nonverbal shame, although there was not a significant relationship for neglect. In addition, Alessandri & Lewis (1996) found girls coded as maltreated to have higher nonverbal shame. More generally, negative or harsh parenting has been associated with the propensity to experience shame (Alessandri & Lewis 1993, 1996; Ferguson & Stegge 1995; Mills 2003). Stuewig & McCloskey (2005) report a relationship between harsh parenting in childhood and shame-proneness in adolescence, a relationship that was mediated by rejecting parenting practices also measured in adolescence.

The relationship between sexual abuse and shame seems to be less straightforward. In research studies of individuals who have experienced sexual abuse, shame has been consistently implicated in poor outcomes such as depression and PTSD symptoms (Feiring & Taska 2005; Feiring et al. 1996, 2002; Talbot et al. 2004). Feiring & Taska (2005) have also found abuse-specific shame to be moderately stable across time.

However, neither Alessandri & Lewis (1996), using observational measures of shame, nor Stuewig & McCloskey (2005), using self-reports of shame-proneness, found a relationship between history of sexual abuse and shame, but both studied small samples of sexually abused individuals. Another reason for these null findings may be that complex emotions surround not only the abusive act but also how the individual copes with the experience. Using facial coding data for shame, Bonanno et al. (2002) found that individuals with a documented history of sexual abuse who did not disclose the abuse in an interview had higher levels of observed shame than those individuals who did disclose their sexual abuse history. There was no difference in shame between those who did disclose and a nonabused comparison group. In a follow-up (Negrao et al. 2005), individuals who did disclose their sexual abuse history were higher on shame coded from narratives compared with those who did not disclose and those in a nonabused comparison group. In other words, individuals who disclosed their abuse histories expressed more shame verbally, whereas those who did not disclose expressed more shame nonverbally, relative to control participants.

In sum, the findings regarding the relationship between childhood abuse and subsequent difficulties with shame are mixed, no doubt due in part to the fact that studies have employed different measures and conceptualizations of both maltreatment and shame (Berliner 2005). Nonetheless, taken together, the weight of evidence suggests that people who experience maltreatment in childhood are somewhat more vulnerable to shame issues later in life.

Vicarious or “collective” shame and guilt: group-based self-conscious emotion

Thus far, this review has focused almost exclusively on shame and guilt experienced in reaction to one’s own misdeeds. In recent years, a number of investigators have substantially expanded the literature on self-conscious emotions by considering “vicarious” or “group-based” shame and guilt—feelings experienced in response to the transgressions and failures of other individuals. This research represents an exciting integration of self-conscious emotions theory with the social psychological literature on social identity, group, and intergroup processes. To the extent that the self is, in part, defined by our interpersonal relations and group memberships, it is possible to construe the behavior of an in-group member as reflecting on the self. Thus, personal causality is not always a prerequisite for the experience of shame or guilt.

In many ways, the phenomena of vicarious shame and guilt parallel personal shame and guilt experiences. Lickel, Schmader, and colleagues (Lickel et al. 2004, 2005) have developed a process model linking specific types of appraisals with vicarious experiences of shame and guilt, respectively. They present compelling evidence that group-based shame is most likely elicited when a threatened shared identity is salient—that is, when concerns about maintaining a positive group identity arise. Vicarious guilt, on the other hand, is more likely when one’s interpersonal dependence with the perpetrator is salient, and when relational-based concerns are highlighted by a focus on harm to another group or individual. For example, Lickel et al. (2005) found that vicarious shame (but not guilt) experiences were positively related to their ratings of the relevance of an offending behavior to the identity shared by the respondent and the perpetrator. The link between identity concerns and vicarious or group-based shame are evident in both correlational and experimental studies (Iyer et al. 2006, Schmader & Lickel 2006).”

My response: This is all highly technical, and I am out of my depth, but I could envision that collective shame could warp a community of joiners. If we teach our young to feel guilty about their bad behaviors and seek to clean up their behaviors as a route to veridical self-esteeming, then we move the children out of an orientation to group-thinking, group-identifying and group-valuing towards individual thinking, individual-identifying and individual-valuing. Thus, the child will act better, be better able to esteem herself and thus love herself and act better more often towards herself and others, a significant moral victory.

A1: “Degree of interdependence with the perpetrator appears to be uniquely related to vicarious guilt (Lickel et al. 2005). However, identification with the perpetrating group can also have implications for vicarious, group-based guilt as well (Branscombe & Doosje 2004, Doosje et al. 1998), especially when individuals are prompted to focus on the harm done (Iyer et al. 2003)

Of particular applied relevance to current international conflicts, when people are provided with ambiguous information about group members’ transgressions, those who are highly identified with the group appear to capitalize on the ambiguity, reporting less vicarious shame (Johns et al. 2005) and group-based guilt (Doosje et al. 1998) relative to those who are less identified, and whose self is presumably less threatened.

As with personal guilt experiences, group-based guilt has been associated with empathy (Zebel et al. 2004) and a motivation to repair or make amends (Iyer et al. 2003, Lickel et al. 2005, Swim & Miller 1999, Zebel et al. 2004). And as with personal shame experiences, vicarious group-based shame (but not guilt) has been linked to a desire to distance oneself from the shame-eliciting event (Johns et al. 2005, Lickel et al. 2005). Furthermore, the link between anger and shame is evident when considering vicarious shame (Iyer et al. 2006, Johns et al. 2005, Schmader & Lickel 2006). Nonetheless, there are some indications that vicarious or group-based shame may have a kinder, gentler side than personal shame. For example, under some circumstances, group-based shame appears to motivate a desire to change the image of the group in a proactive fashion (Lickel et al. 2006).

Embarrassment

Embarrassment appears to be less centrally relevant to the domain of morality than are shame and guilt. For example, adults’ ratings of personal shame-, guilt-, and embarrassment-eliciting events indicate that when people feel embarrassed, they are less concerned with issues of morality than when they feel shame or guilt (Tangney et al. 1996a). Nonetheless, certain conditions exist under which embarrassment may support or undermine people’s efforts to live life in a manner consistent with their moral standards.

Miller (1995) defines embarrassment as “an aversive state of mortification, abashment, and chagrin that follows public social predicaments” (p. 322). Embarrassment accounts from hundreds of high school students and adults (Miller 1992) indicate that the most common causes of embarrassment are “normative public deficiencies”—situations in which a person behaves in a clumsy, absent-minded, or hapless way (tripping in front of a crowd, forgetting someone’s name, unintended bodily-induced noises). Other common embarrassment-inducing situations include awkward social interactions and being conspicuous (e.g., during the “birthday” song). Generally, events causing embarrassment seem to signal that something is amiss— some aspect of the self or one’s behavior needs to be carefully monitored, hidden, or changed.

The motivations prompted by embarrassment, however, may have implications for moral behavior. Research indicates that embarrassed people are inclined to behave in conciliatory ways in order to win approval and (re)inclusion from others (Cupach & Metts 1990, 1992; Leary et al. 1996; Miller 1996; Sharkey & Stafford 1990). In other words, upon feeling embarrassment (or to avoid embarrassment), people are inclined to conform and curry favor. Thus, depending on the local norms of the immediate social environment, embarrassment may prompt adherence to broadly accepted moral standards or to locally endorsed deviant acts.

As with shame and guilt, there are individual differences in the degree to which people are prone to experience embarrassment. Research has shown that embarrassability is associated with neuroticism, high levels of negative affect, self-consciousness, and a fear of negative evaluation from others (Edelmann & McCusker 1986, Leary & Meadows 1991, Miller 1995b). To the extent that embarrassment-prone individuals are highly aware of and concerned with social rules and standards, they may be especially vulnerable to the influence of peer pressure.”

 

My response: It is useful to feel embarrassed when one goofs up in social settings, but one must control the self, not the pack so we do not want increased influence by peer pressure to avoid being embarrassed, the price being to sin with the pack.

A1: “Moral Pride

Thus far, this chapter has focused on negatively valenced moral emotions. We turn now to one of the long-neglected positively valenced moral emotions—morally relevant experiences of pride. Of the self-conscious emotions, pride is the neglected sibling. Mascolo & Fischer (1995) define pride as an emotion “generated by appraisals that one is responsible for a socially valued outcome or for being a socially valued person” (p. 66). From their perspective, pride serves to enhance people’s self-worth and, perhaps more importantly, to encourage future behavior that conforms to social standards of worth or merit (see also Barrett 1995).”

 

My response: As an egoist, I have long argued that individual positive, merited pride is not only not Luciferian or the worship of one’s human intellect, which Jordan Peterson rails against, positive, merited self-pride is a motivating, powerful force at work in the active, strong personal conscience. The individual pursues his enlightened self-interest, but he must act morally, loving towards himself or others, and if and when he falls short, he feels guilty and must amend and regain his moral footing. He will behave more than not for negative reasons that he does not want to feel and be self-humiliated. Via positive reasons, he will do well because it is rewarding to have met high moral and personal behavioral standards, so now he is able to feel veridically self-esteeming because he has lived and acted according to his high and strict moral code.

A1: “Most theoretical and empirical research on pride emphasizes achievement-oriented pride (Tracy & Robins 2004b). Although pride may most often arise in response to scholastic, occupational, or athletic achievement, self-conscious experiences of pride in moral contexts may be an important component of our moral emotional apparatus. Feelings of pride for meeting or exceeding morally relevant standards (and for inhibiting impulses to behave immorally) may serve important motivational functions, rewarding and reinforcing one’s commitment to ethics of autonomy, community, and divinity.

In parallel to the self-versus-behavior distinction of guilt and shame, it may be useful to distinguish between two types of pride. Along similar lines, Tangney (1990) distinguished between “alpha” pride (pride in self) and “beta” pride (pride in behavior), M.Lewis (1992) distinguished between hubris (pride-fulness) and pride (experienced in reference to a specific action or behavior), and Tracy & Robins (2004b) distinguished between hubris and more event-specific achievement-oriented pride. Tracy & Robins (2006), drawing on multiple methods, present compelling empirical evidence for these two types of pride.”

My response: I give these researchers credit for devising two categories for pride, a positive kind and a negative kind. Pride in the self may be based on merit or not, but pride in excellent behavior is more solid and positive, and I would insert that positive pride is egoistic and merited, and empty, negative pride is based on group-affiliation, not personal achievement.

A1: “Little empirical research has been conducted on individual differences in proneness to pride in self (or pride in behavior, for that matter). The Tests of Self-Conscious Affect (e.g., Tangney et al. 1989; see Tangney & Dearing 2002 for details) each contain measures of the propensity to experience alpha pride and beta pride, respectively. These sub-scales, however, have very modest reliabilities, largely because they draw on only a few items. Thus, we and other investigators have made little use of these ancillary scales. Lewis (1992) views hubris as largely maladaptive, noting that hubristic individuals are inclined to distort and invent situations to enhance the self, which can lead to interpersonal problems. It remains to be seen how individual differences in pride or hubris relate to the capacity to self-regulate or to choose the moral path in life. One possibility is that pride and hubris represent the flip side of guilt and shame—one the “modern,” adaptive moral emotion and the other, its evil twin.

OTHER-FOCUSED MORAL EMOTIONS

Thus far, our review of theory and research on moral emotion has focused on the self-conscious emotions of shame, guilt, embarrassment, and pride. These emotions vary in valence and in attributions regarding the particular source of offense (e.g., self versus self’s behavior). But these self-conscious emotions are similar in that in each case, the emotion is elicited when some aspect of the self is scrutinized and evaluated with respect to moral standards. Recently, Haidt (2000, 2003) added importantly to our thinking about the nature of “moral emotions.” In his work, Haidt focuses primarily on the emotions of elevation and gratitude—emotions that are experienced when observing the admirable deeds of others, and that then motivate observers to engage in admirable deeds themselves.

In fact, by crossing the two dimensions of focus (self versus other) and valence (positive versus negative), one can conceptualize four categories of moral emotion (see Haidt 2003, following Ortony et al. 1988). To date most theory and research on moral affect has emphasized the negatively valenced self-conscious quadrant. With the advent of the positive psychology movement and Haidt’s groundbreaking work, we anticipate that the next decade will see exciting new developments in our understanding of the moral functions of negatively and positively valenced other-directed emotions.

Righteous Anger, Contempt, and Disgust

Anger is a negatively valenced, other-focused emotion not typically considered in the morally relevant sphere. People may experience anger for a very broad range of situations—e.g., when insulted, frustrated, inconvenienced, or injured in any one of a number of ways. According to appraisal theorists (Lazarus 1991, Roseman 1991, Smith & Ellsworth 1985), people typically feel angry when they appraise an event as personally relevant, inconsistent with their goals, and when the event appears to be caused (often intentionally) by a responsible other. The emphasis is on perceptions of actual or potential self-harm (e.g., a personally relevant goal has been thwarted or frustrated, a valued possession has been threatened or harmed) in conjunction with attributions of intentionality and/or responsibility on the part of the offending other.

Righteous anger, however, arises in response to a special class of anger-eliciting events, those in which the perpetrator’s behavior represents a violation of moral standards. In such cases, the harm need not be personally experienced. One can feel anger upon witnessing morally repulsive behavior aimed at a third party. Rozin et al. (1999) presented evidence that righteous anger tends to occur more specifically in response to violations of the ethic of autonomy—the ethic most familiar in Western culture. Righteous anger can serve moral functions in that it can motivate “third-party” bystanders to take action in order to remedy observed injustices.

The emotions of contempt and disgust also stem from negative evaluations of others, but seem somewhat less apt than righteous anger to motivate morally corrective action. Among participants in both the United States and Japan, Rozin et al. (1999) found that feelings of contempt were differentially linked to violations of the ethic of community (e.g., violations of social hierarchy), whereas feelings of disgust were linked to violations of the ethic of divinity (e.g., actions that remind us of our animal nature, such as defecation, problems with hygiene, etc., as well as assaults on human dignity, such as racism and abuse).

Elevation

Just as disgust is the moral emotion people experience when observing violations of the ethic of divinity, elevation is the positive emotion elicited when observing others behaving in a particularly virtuous, commendable, or superhuman way (Haidt 2000). In a study of college students, Haidt et al. (2002) explored the phenomenology of elevation, asking participants to recall “a manifestation of humanity’s ‘higher’ or ‘better’ nature.” Participants reported warm, pleasant, “tingling” feelings in their chest, they felt open to other people as their attention turned outward, and they felt motivated to help others and to become better people themselves. In this respect, elevation appears to be the quintessential positive emotion, especially apt to foster a “broaden and build” (Frederickson 2000) orientation to the world.”

My response: Elevation seems reasonable, that we are moved to act better after observing the example of exemplary neighbors around us.

 

There is also an individualistic version of this, that as we habitually behave commendably, that make us feel proud and good, and we like the feeling, so we continue to act in a way commensurate with and which elicits that desirable feeling.

A1: “Gratitude

Gratitude is another example of an other-oriented, positively valenced moral affect. People are inclined to feel gratitude specifically in response to another person’s benevolence—that is, when they are the recipient of benefits provided by another, especially when those benefits are unexpected and/or costly to the benefactor. Gratitude is a pleasant affective state, distinct from indebtedness, which implies an obligation and is often experienced as a negative state.

McCullough et al. (2001) classify gratitude as a moral affect, not because the experience and expression of gratitude is in and of itself “moral,” but because feelings of gratitude (a) result from moral (e.g., prosocial, helping) behavior of the benefactor, and (b) engender subsequent moral motivation on the part of recipients. They observe that grateful people are often motivated to respond prosocially— both to their benefactor and toward others not involved in the gratitude-eliciting act. Moreover, expressions of gratitude can serve as a moral reinforcer, encouraging benefactors’ helping behavior in the future (Bennett et al. 1996, Clark et al. 1988, Goldman et al. 1982).

Gratitude not only benefits benefactors and relationships. Those who benefit most from the experience and expression of gratitude are grateful people themselves. In a series of experimental studies, feelings of gratitude enhanced psychological resilience, physical health, and the quality of daily life (Emmons & McCullough 2003). In fact, both dispositional and situation-specific episodes of gratitude have been linked to psychological well-being and adaptive behavior in non-clinical samples (Emmons & Shelton 2002; Frederickson et al. 2003; Kendler et al. 2003; McCullough et al. 2001, 2002) and among combat veterans with PTSD (Kashdan et al. 2006).

EMPATHY: A MORAL EMOTIONAL PROCESS

Finally, we discuss briefly a morally relevant emotional process—other-oriented empathy. (For a more complete review, see Eisenberg et al. 2004, 2006.) In contrast to the other moral emotions discussed in this review, empathy is not a discrete emotion. Rather it is an emotional process with substantial implications for moral behavior. Current conceptualizations of empathy integrate both affective and cognitive components. Feshbach (1975), for example, defines empathy as a “shared emotional response between an observer and a stimulus person.” She suggests that empathic responsiveness requires three interrelated skills or capacities: (a) the cognitive ability to take another person’s perspective, (b) the cognitive ability to accurately recognize and discriminate another person’s affective experience, and (c) the affective ability to personally experience a range of emotions (since empathy involves sharing another person’s emotional experience). Similarly, Coke and colleagues (1978) proposed a two-stage model of empathic responding, whereby perspective-taking facilitates empathic concern, which in turn leads to a desire to help.

Some researchers have made a distinction between “true” empathy and sympathy. Eisenberg (1986) explains that sympathy involves feelings of concern for the emotional state of another, but does not necessarily involve the vicarious experience of the other person’s feelings or emotions (e.g., emotional matching). Thus, one may feel concern (sympathy) for an angered individual without being vicariously angered oneself (an empathic reaction).

Others have distinguished between other-oriented empathy and self-oriented personal distress (Batson 1990, Batson & Coke 1981, Davis 1983). Other-oriented empathy involves taking another person’s perspective and vicariously experiencing similar feelings. These responses often involve feelings of sympathy and concern for the other person, and often lead to helping behavior. Importantly, the empathic individual’s focus remains on the experiences and needs of the other person, not on his or her own empathic response. In contrast, self-oriented personal distress involves a primary focus on the feelings, needs, and experiences of the empathizer. Empirical research underscores the importance of this distinction. Empathic concern for others has been linked to altruistic helping behavior, whereas self-oriented personal distress is unrelated to altruism (Batson et al. 1988) and may in fact inter-fere with prosocial behavior (Davis&Oathout 1987; Eisenberg et al. 1990, 1993; Estrada 1995).

Empathy and its close cousin sympathy have been cited as central to the human moral affective system for at least three reasons (Eisenberg et al. 2004, 2006). First, empathic reactions to others’ distress often elicit feelings of concern for the distressed other (Feshbach 1975). Second, such empathic concern often prompts behavior aimed at helping the distressed other (Batson 1991, Eisenberg & Miller 1987, Feshbach 1987). Third, feelings of empathy are apt to inhibit aggression and other behaviors that are harmful to others (Feshbach & Feshbach 1969, Miller & Eisenberg 1988).”

My response: I did not spend much time on this sentiment of empathy and its close cousin sympathy, but my hunch is that if the self-loving egoist loves himself and is empathetic towards his needs, faults, and areas requiring improvement, that is the best avenue to take to learn, show and enjoy applying one’s inner feeling of well-being and happiness to the needs and plights of one’s neighbors: no one can show sympathy and empathy towards a neighbor like an individuated egoist can.

A1: “SUMMARY AND FUTURE DIRECTIONS FOR RESEARCH

This review has considered the implications of moral standards and moral emotion for moral decisions and moral behavior. In this sense, the structure of this review reflects the current state of the field. Little research has examined the relation between moral standards and moral emotional factors, much less their interactive influence in moderating the link between moral standards and people’s moral behavior. Our hope is that this framework will encourage integrated research along such exciting lines. Future directions for research include evaluating the relative importance of cognitive and emotional factors in various domains of morality, as well as the degree to which particular emotional factors are differentially more important in influencing behavior among particular subpopulations (e.g., corporate managers, criminal offenders) and at different points in development.”

My response: I wish to repeat that cognitive or rational morals being highlighted, along with secondary placing for affective or emotional morals, should, within egoist ethics, help people better close the gap between their moral ideals and their personal choices and behavior.

A1: “In addition, this review may help clarify several points of conceptual confusion evident in portions of the literature. For example, in the guilt literature, some theory and associated measures have confounded proneness to guilt with moral standards or other related attitudes and beliefs (e.g., Mosher 1966; see Tangney 1996 for discussion). Although feelings of guilt generally arise from some failure or violation of moral standards, proneness to guilt (an affective disposition) is conceptually distinct from moral standards (a set of beliefs guiding one’s evaluation of behavior). With the advantage of greater conceptual clarity, future researchers can address many questions about the functions and costs of various forms of moral emotion. Such research has potential to pay off substantially, informing educational, judicial, and social policies that foster adaptive moral processes and ultimately moral behavior that benefits all.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

This research was supported by grant #RO1 DA14694 to the first author from the National Institute on Drug Abuse. Many thanks to Laura Harty, Walt Swenson, and members of the Human Emotions Research Lab for their assistance.

Contributor Information

June Price Tangney, Email: jtangney@gmu.edu.

Jeff Stuewig, Email: jstuewig@gmu.edu.

Debra J. Mashek, Email: mashek@hmc.edu.

LITERATURE CITED

  1. Ajzen I. The theory of planned behavior. Org. Behav. Hum. Decis. Process. 1991;50:179–211. [Google Scholar]
  2. Alessandri S, Lewis M. Parental evaluation and its relation to shame and pride in young children. Sex Roles. 1993;29:335–343. [Google Scholar]
  3. Alessandri S, Lewis M. Differences in pride and shame in maltreated and nonmaltreated preschoolers. Child Dev. 1996;67:1857–1869. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  4. Andrews B. Bodily shame as a mediator between abusive experiences and depression. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 1995;104:277–285. doi: 10.1037//0021-843x.104.2.277. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  5. Andrews B. Shame and childhood abuse. In: Gilbert P, Andrews B, editors. Shame: Interpersonal Behavior, Psychopathology, and Culture. Series in Affective Science. New York: Oxford Univ. Press; 1998. pp. 176–190. [Google Scholar]
  6. Andrews B, Brewin CR, Rose S, Kirk M. Predicting PTSD symptomsin victimsofviolent crime: the role of shame, anger, and childhood abuse. J. Abnorm. Psychol. 2000;109:69–73. doi: 10.1037//0021-843x.109.1.69. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  7. Andrews B, Hunter E. Shame, early abuse, and course of depression in a clinical sample: preliminary study. Cogn. Emot. 1997;11(4):373–381. [Google Scholar]
  8. Ashby JS, Rice KG, Martin JL. Perfectionism, shame, and depressive symptoms. J. Couns. Dev. 2006;84(2):148–156. [Google Scholar]
  9. Barrett KC. A functionalist approach to shame and guilt. See Tangney & Fischer. 1995:25–63. [Google Scholar]
  10. Batson CD. How social an animal? The human capacity for caring. Am. Psychol. 1990;45:336–346. [Google Scholar]
  11. Batson CD. The Altruism Question. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; 1991. [Google Scholar]
  12. Batson CD, Coke JS. Empathy: a source of altruistic motivation for helping? In: Rushton JP, Sorrentino RM, editors. Altruism and Helping Behavior: Social, Personality, and Developmental Perspectives. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; 1981. pp. 167–187. [Google Scholar]
  13. Batson CD, Dyck JL, Brandt JR, Batson JG, Powell AL, et al. Five studies testing two new egoistic alternatives to the empathy-altruism hypothesis. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1988;55:52–77. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.55.1.52. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  14. Baumeister RF, Stillwell AM, Heatherton TF. Guilt: an interpersonal approach. Psychol. Bull. 1994;115:243–267. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.115.2.243. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  15. Baumeister RF, Stillwell AM, Heatherton TF. Interpersonal aspects of guilt: evidence from narrative studies. See Tangney & Fischer. 1995a:255–273. [Google Scholar]
  16. Baumeister RF, Stillwell AM, Heatherton TF. Personal narratives about guilt: role in action control and interpersonal relationships. Basic Appl. Soc. Psychol. 1995b;17:173–198. [Google Scholar]
  17. Benedict R. The Chrysanthemum and the Sword. Boston: Houghton Mifflin; 1946. [Google Scholar]
  18. Bennett DS, Sullivan MW, Lewis M. Young children’s adjustment as a function of maltreatment, shame, and anger. Child Maltreat. 2005;10(4):311–323. doi: 10.1177/1077559505278619. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  19. Bennett L, Ross MW, Sunderland R. The relationship between recognition, rewards, and burnout in AIDS caregiving. AIDS Care. 1996;8:145–153. doi: 10.1080/09540129650125830. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  20. Berghold K, Locke J. Assessing guilt in adolescents with anorexia nervosa. Am. J. Psychother. 2002;56(3):378–390. doi: 10.1176/appi.psychotherapy.2002.56.3.378. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  21. Berliner L. Shame in child maltreatment: contributions and caveats. Child Maltreat. 2005;10:387–390. doi: 10.1177/1077559505281161. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  22. Blacher R. “It isn’t fair”: postoperative depression and other manifestations of survivor guilt. Gen. Hosp. Psychiatry. 2000;22(1):43–48. doi: 10.1016/s0163-8343(99)00059-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  23. Blatt S. Levels of object representation in anaclitic and introjective depression. Psychoanal. Study Child. 1974;29:107–157. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  24. Bonanno G, Keltner D, Noll J. When the face reveals what words do not: facial expressions of emotions, smiling, and the willingness to disclose childhood sexual abuse. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2002;83(1):94–110. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  25. Boye Bentson Malt. Does guilt proneness predict acute and long-term distress in relatives of patients with schizophrenia? Acta Psychiatr. Scand. 2002;106:351–357. doi: 10.1034/j.1600-0447.2002.02276.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  26. Branscombe NR, Doojse B. Collective Guilt: International Perspectives. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press; 2004. [Google Scholar]
  27. Brewin CR, Andrews B, Rose S. Fear, helplessness, and horror in posttraumatic stress disorder: investigating DSM-IV criterion A2 in victims of violent crime. J. Trauma. Stress. 2000;13:499–509. doi: 10.1023/A:1007741526169. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  28. Campbell JS, Elison J. Shame coping styles and psychopathic personality traits. J. Personal. Assess. 2005;84:96–104. doi: 10.1207/s15327752jpa8401_16. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  29. Clark HB, Northrop JT, Barkshire CT. The effects of contingent thank-you notes on case managers’ visiting residential clients. Educ. Treat. Child. 1988;11:45–51. [Google Scholar]
  30. Coke JS, Batson CD, McDavis K. Empathic mediation of helping: a two-stage model. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1978;36:752–766. [Google Scholar]
  31. Crossley D, Rockett K. The experience of shame in older psychiatric patients: a preliminary enquiry. Aging Mental Health. 2005;9:368–373. doi: 10.1080/13607860500131252. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  32. Cupach WR, Metts S. Remedial processes in embarrassing predicaments. In: Anderson J, editor. Communication Yearbook 13. Newbury Park, CA: Sage; 1990. pp. 323–352. [Google Scholar]
  33. Cupach WR, Metts S. The effects of type of predicament and embarrassability on remedial responses to embarrassing situations. Commun. Q. 1992;40:149–161. [Google Scholar]
  34. Davis MH. Measuring individual differences in empathy: evidence for a multidimensional approach. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1983;44:113–126. [Google Scholar]
  35. Davis MH, Oathout HA. Maintenance of satisfaction in romantic relationships: empathy and relational competence. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1987;53:397–410. [Google Scholar]
  36. Dearing RL, Stuewig J, Tangney JP. On the importance of distinguishing shame from guilt: relations to problematic alcohol and drug use. Addict. Behav. 2005;30:1392–1404. doi: 10.1016/j.addbeh.2005.02.002. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  37. Deblinger E, Runyon M. Understanding and treating feelings of shame in children who have experienced maltreatment. Child Maltreat. 2005;10(4):364–376. doi: 10.1177/1077559505279306. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  38. DeVisser RO, Smith AMA. Which intention? Whose intention? Condom use and theories of individual decision making. Psychol. Health Med. 2004;9:193–204. [Google Scholar]
  39. Dickerson SS, Gruenaewald TL, Kemeny ME. When the social self is threatened: shame, physiology, and health. J. Personal. 2004a;72:1191–1216. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-6494.2004.00295.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  40. Dickerson SS, Kemeny ME, Aziz N, Kim KH, Fahey JL. Immunological effects of induced shame and guilt. Psychosom. Med. 2004b;66:124–131. doi: 10.1097/01.psy.0000097338.75454.29. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  41. Doojse B, Branscombe NR, Spears R, Manstead ASR. Guilty by association: when one’s group has a negative history. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1998;75:872–886. [Google Scholar]
  42. Edelmann RJ, McCusker G. Introversion, neuroticism, empathy, and embarrassability. Personal. Individ. Differ. 1986;7:133–140. [Google Scholar]
  43. Eisenberg N. Altruistic Cognition, Emotion, and Behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; 1986. [Google Scholar]
  44. Eisenberg N, Fabes RA, Carlo G, Speer AL, Switzer G, et al. The relations of empathy-related emotions and maternal practices to children’s comforting behavior. J. Exp. Child Psychol. 1993;55:131–150. doi: 10.1006/jecp.1993.1007. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  45. Eisenberg N, Fabes RA, Miller PA, Shell R, Shea C, Mayplumlee T. Pre-schoolers’ vicarious emotional responding and their situational and dispositional prosocial behavior. Merrill-Palmer Q. 1990;36:507–529. [Google Scholar]
  46. Eisenberg N, Miller PA. Empathy, sympathy, and altruism: empirical and conceptual links. In: Eisenberg N, Strayer J, editors. Empathy and Its Development. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press; 1987. pp. 292–316. [Google Scholar]
  47. Eisenberg N, Spinrad TL, Sadovsky A. Empathy-related responding in children. In: Killen M, Smetana JG, editors. Handbook of Moral Development. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; 2006. pp. 517–549. [Google Scholar]
  48. Eisenberg N, Valiente C, Champion C. Empathy-related responding: moral, social, and socialization correlates. In: Miller AG, editor. The Social Psychology of Good and Evil. New York: Guilford; 2004. pp. 386–415. [Google Scholar]
  49. Elison J, Lennon R, Pulos S. Investigating the compass of shame: the development of the compass of shame scale. Soc. Behav. Personal. 2006a;34:221–238. [Google Scholar]
  50. Elison J, Pulos S, Lennon R. Shame-focused coping: an empirical study of the Compass of Shame. Soc. Behav. Personal. 2006b;34:161–168. [Google Scholar]
  51. Ellis A. Reason and Emotion in Psychotherapy. New York: Lyle Stuart; 1962. [Google Scholar]
  52. Emmons RA, McCullough ME. Counting blessings versus burdens: an experimental investigation of gratitude and subjective well-being in daily life. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2003;84:377–389. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.84.2.377. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  53. Emmons RA, Shelton CS. Gratitude and the science of positive psychology. In: Snyder CR, Lopez SJ, editors. Handbook of Positive Psychology. New York: Oxford Univ. Press; 2002. pp. 459–471. [Google Scholar]
  54. Estrada P. Adolescents’ self-reports of prosocial responses to friends and acquaintances: the role of sympathy-related cognitive, affective, and motivational processes. J. Res. Adolesc. 1995;5:173–200. [Google Scholar]
  55. Feiring C, Taska L. The persistence of shame following sexual abuse: a longitudinal look at risk and recovery. Child Maltreat. 2005;10:337–349. doi: 10.1177/1077559505276686. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  56. Feiring C, Taska L, Lewis M. A process model for understanding adaptation to sexual abuse: the role of shame in defining stigmatization. Child Abuse Neglect. 1996;20:767–782. doi: 10.1016/0145-2134(96)00064-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  57. Feiring C, Taska L, Lewis M. Adjustment following sexual abuse discovery: the role of shame and attributional style. Dev. Psychol. 2002;38:79–92. doi: 10.1037//0012-1649.38.1.79. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  58. Ferguson TJ, Stegge H. Emotional states and traits in children: the case of guilt and shame. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:174–197. [Google Scholar]
  59. Ferguson TJ, Stegge H, Damhuis I. Children’s understanding of guilt and shame. Child Dev. 1991;62:827–839. [Google Scholar]
  60. Ferguson TJ, Stegge H, Eyre HL, Vollmer R, Ashbaker M. Context effects and the (mal)adaptive nature of guilt and shame in children. Genet. Soc. Gen. Psychol. Monogr. 2000;126:319–345. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  61. Ferguson TJ, Stegge H, Miller ER, Olsen ME. Guilt, shame, and symptoms in children. Dev. Psychol. 1999;35:347–357. doi: 10.1037//0012-1649.35.2.347. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  62. Feshbach ND. Empathy in children: some theoretical and empirical considerations. Couns. Psychol. 1975;5:25–30. [Google Scholar]
  63. Feshbach ND. Parental empathy and child adjustment/maladjustment. In: Eisenberg N, Strayer J, editors. Empathy and Its Development. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press; 1987. pp. 271–291. [Google Scholar]
  64. Feshbach ND, Feshbach S. The relationship between empathy and aggression in two age groups. Dev. Psychol. 1969;1:102–107. [Google Scholar]
  65. Fontana A, Rosenbeck R. Trauma, change in strength of religious faith, and mental health service use among veterans treated for PTSD. J. Nerv. Ment. Dis. 2004;192:579–584. doi: 10.1097/01.nmd.0000138224.17375.55. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  66. Frederickson BL. Cultivating positive emotions to optimize well-being and health. Prevent. Treat. 2000;vol. 3 article 0001a. [Google Scholar]
  67. Frederickson BL, Roberts T. Objectification theory: toward understanding women’s lived experiences and mental health risks. Psychol. Women Q. 1997;21:173–206. [Google Scholar]
  68. Frederickson BL, Tugade MM, Waugh CE, Larkin GR. What good are positive emotions in crises? A prospective study of resilience and emotions following the terrorist attacks on the United States on September 11, 2001. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2003;84:365–376. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.84.2.365. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  69. Freud S. The dissolution of the Oedipus complex. In: Strachey J, translator. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Vol. 19. London: Hogarth; 1961/1924. pp. 173–182. [Google Scholar]
  70. Ghatavi K, Nicolson R, MacDonald C, Osher S, Levitt A. Defining guilt in depression: a comparison of subjects with major depression, chronic medical illness and healthy controls. J. Affect. Disord. 2002;68:307–315. doi: 10.1016/s0165-0327(01)00335-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  71. Gilbert P, Allan S, Goss K. Parental representations, shame, interpersonal problems, and vulnerability to psychopathology. Clin. Psychol. Psychother. 1996;3:23–24. [Google Scholar]
  72. Goldman M, Seever M, Seever M. Social labeling and the foot-in-the-door effect. J. Soc. Psychol. 1982;117:19–23. [Google Scholar]
  73. Gramzow R, Tangney JP. Proneness to shame and the narcissistic personality. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 1992;18:369–376. [Google Scholar]
  74. Gruenewald TL, Kemeny ME, Aziz N, Fahey JL. Acute threat to the social self: shame, social self-esteem, and cortisol activity. Psychosom. Med. 2004;66:915–924. doi: 10.1097/01.psy.0000143639.61693.ef. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  75. Haidt J. The positive emotion of elevation. Prevent. Treat. 2000;Vol. 3:1522–3736. ISSN. [Google Scholar]
  76. Haidt J. Elevation and the positive psychology of morality. In: Keyes CL, Haidt J, editors. Flourishing: Positive Psychology and the Life Well-Lived. Washington, DC: Am. Psychol. Assoc; 2003. pp. 275–289. [Google Scholar]
  77. Haidt J, Algoe S, Meijer Z, Tam A. Elevation: An Emotion That Makes People Want to Do Good Deeds. Charlottesville: Univ. Virginia; 2002. Unpubl. manuscr. [Google Scholar]
  78. Hallsworth L, Wade TD, Tiggemann M. Individual differences in male body image: an examination of self-objectification in recreational body builders. Br. J. Health Psychol. 2005;10:453–465. doi: 10.1348/135910705X26966. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  79. Harder DW. Shame and guilt assessment, and relationships of shame- and guilt-proneness to psychopathology. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:368–392. [Google Scholar]
  80. Hare RD. The Hare Psychopathy Checklist-Revised. Toronto: Multi-Health Syst; 1991. [Google Scholar]
  81. Harper FWK, Arias I. The role of shame in predicting adult anger and depressive symptoms among victims of child psychological maltreatment. J. Fam. Violence. 2004;19(6):367–375. [Google Scholar]
  82. Harper FWK, Austin AG, Cercone JJ, Arias I. The role of shame, anger, and affect regulation in men’s perpetration of psychological abuse in dating relationships. J. Interpers. Violence. 2005;20:1648–1662. doi: 10.1177/0886260505278717. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  83. Harris H. Reassessing the dimensionality of the moral emotions. Br. J. Psychol. 2003;94:457–473. doi: 10.1348/000712603322503033. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  84. Hartmann E, Loewenstein R. Notes on the superego. Psychoanal. Study Child. 1962;17:42–81. [Google Scholar]
  85. Henderson L, Zimbardo P. Shyness as a clinical condition: the Stanford model. In: Crozier WR, Alden LE, editors. International Handbook of Social Anxiety: Concepts, Research and Interventions Relating to the Self and Shyness. New York: Wiley; 2001. pp. 431–447. [Google Scholar]
  86. Herrald MM, Tomaka J. Patterns of emotion-specific appraisal, coping, and cardiovascular reactivity during an ongoing emotional episode. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2002;83:434–450. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  87. Hoffman ML. Development of prosocial motivation: empathy and guilt. In: Eisenberg-Berg N, editor. Development of Prosocial Behavior. New York: Academic; 1982. pp. 281–313. [Google Scholar]
  88. Hoglund C, Nicholas K. Shame, guilt, and anger in college students exposed to abusive family environments. J. Fam. Violence. 1995;10:141–157. [Google Scholar]
  89. Iyer A, Leach CW, Crosby FJ. White guilt and racial compensation: the benefits and limits of self-focus. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 2003;29:117–129. doi: 10.1177/0146167202238377. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  90. Iyer A, Schmader T, Lickel B. Predicting American and British opposition to the occupation of Iraq: the role of group-based anger, shame, and guilt. 2006 Unpubl. manuscr. [Google Scholar]
  91. Johns M, Schmader T, Lickel B. Ashamed to be an American? The role of identification in predicting vicarious shame for anti-Arab prejudice after 9–11. Self Ident. 2005;4:331–348. [Google Scholar]
  92. Joireman J. Empathy and the self-absorption paradox II: self-rumination and self-reflection as mediators between shame, guilt, and empathy. Self Ident. 2004;3:225–238. [Google Scholar]
  93. Jones WH, Kugler K. Interpersonal correlates of the Guilt Inventory. J. Personal. Assess. 1993;61:246–258. doi: 10.1207/s15327752jpa6102_6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  94. Kashdan TB, Uswatte G, Julian T. Gratitude and hedonic and eudaimonic well-being in Vietnam War veterans. Behav. Res. Therapy. 2006;44:177–199. doi: 10.1016/j.brat.2005.01.005. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  95. Keltner D, Buswell BN. Evidence for the distinctness of embarrassment, shame, and guilt: a study of recalled antecedents and facial expressions of emotion. Cogn. Emot. 1996;10:155–171. [Google Scholar]
  96. Kendler KS, Liu X, Gardner CO, McCullough ME, Larson D, Prescott CA. Dimensions of religiosity and their relationship to lifetime psychiatric and substance use disorders. Am. J. Psychiatry. 2003;160:496–503. doi: 10.1176/appi.ajp.160.3.496. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  97. Ketelaar T, Au WT. The effects of feelings of guilt on the behavior of uncooperative individuals in repeated social bargaining games: an affect-as-information interpretation of the role of emotion in social interaction. Cogn. Emot. 2003;17:429–453. doi: 10.1080/02699930143000662. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  98. Kroll J, Egan E. Psychiatry, moral worry, and moral emotions. J. Psychiatr. Pract. 2004;10:352–360. doi: 10.1097/00131746-200411000-00003. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  99. Kubany ES, Abueg FR, Owens JA, Brennan JM, Kaplan AS, Watson SB. Initial examination of a multidimensional model of trauma-related guilt: applications to combat veterans and battered women. J. Psychopathol. Behav. Assess. 1995;17(4):353–376. [Google Scholar]
  100. Kubany ES, Hill EE, Owens JA, Iannce-Spencer C, McCaig MA, et al. Cognitive trauma therapy for battered women with PTSD (CTT-BW) J. Consult. Clin. Psychol. 2004;72(1):3–18. doi: 10.1037/0022-006X.72.1.3. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  101. Latane B, Darley JM. Group inhibition of bystander intervention. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1968;10:215–221. doi: 10.1037/h0026570. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  102. Lazarus RS. Emotion and Adaptation. New York: Oxford Univ. Press; 1991. [Google Scholar]
  103. Leary MR, Landel JL, Patton KM. The motivated expression of embarrassment following a self-presentational predicament. J. Personal. 1996;64:619–637. [Google Scholar]
  104. Leary MR, Meadows S. Predictors, elicitors, and concomitants of social blushing. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1991;60:254–262. [Google Scholar]
  105. Lee D, Scragg P, Turner S. The role of shame and guilt in traumatic events: a clinical model of shame-based and guilt-based PTSD. Br. J. Med. Psychol. 2001;74:451–466. doi: 10.1348/000711201161109. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  106. Leeming D, Boyle M. Shame as a social phenomenon: a critical analysis of the concept of dispositional shame. Psychol. Psychother. Theory Res. Pract. 2004;77:375–396. doi: 10.1348/1476083041839312. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  107. Leith KP, Baumeister RF. Empathy, shame, guilt, and narratives of interpersonal conflicts: guilt-prone people are better at perspective taking. J. Personal. 1998;66:1–37. [Google Scholar]
  108. Leskela J, Dieperink M, Thuras P. Shame and posttraumatic stress disorder. J. Trauma. Stress. 2002;15:223–226. doi: 10.1023/A:1015255311837. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  109. Lewin K. Defining the “filed at a given time.”. Psychol. Rev. 1943;50:292–310. [Google Scholar]
  110. Lewis HB. Shame and Guilt in Neurosis. New York: Int. Univ. Press; 1971. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  111. Lewis M. Shame: The Exposed Self. New York: Free Press; 1992. [Google Scholar]
  112. Lewis M, Ramsay D. Cortisol response to embarrassment and shame. Child Dev. 2002;73:1034–1045. doi: 10.1111/1467-8624.00455. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  113. Lickel B, Schmader T, Barquissau M. The evocation of moral emotions in intergroup contexts: the distinction between collective guilt and collective shame. In: Branscombe NR, Doosje B, editors. Collective Guilt: International Perspectives. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press; 2004. pp. 35–55. [Google Scholar]
  114. Lickel B, Schmader T, Spanovic M. Group-conscious emotions: the implications of others’ wrongdoings for identity and relationships. In: Robins R, Tracy J, Tangney JP, editors. The Self-Conscious Emotions: Theory and Research. New York: Guilford; 2006. In press. [Google Scholar]
  115. Lickel B, Schmader T, Curtis M, Scarnier M, Ames DR. Vicarious shame and guilt. Group Process. Intergroup Relat. 2005;8:145–147. [Google Scholar]
  116. Lindsay-Hartz J. Contrasting experiences of shame and guilt. Am. Behav. Sci. 1984;27:689–704. [Google Scholar]
  117. Marschall DE. Effects of induced shame on subsequent empathy and altruistic behavior. Fairfax, VA: George Mason Univ.; 1996. Unpubl. thesis. [Google Scholar]
  118. Mascolo MF, Fischer KW. Developmental transformations in appraisals for pride, shame, and guilt. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:64–113. [Google Scholar]
  119. McCullough ME, Emmons RA, Tsang J. The grateful disposition: a conceptual and empirical topography. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2002;82:112–127. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.82.1.112. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  120. McCullough ME, Kilpatrick S, Emmons RA, Larson D. Is gratitude a moral effect? Psychol. Bull. 2001;127:249–266. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.127.2.249. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  121. McLaughlin DE. Posttraumatic stress disorder symptoms and self-conscious affect among battered women. Diss. Abstr. Int. B Sci. Eng. 2002;62:4470. [Google Scholar]
  122. Meehan MA, O’Connor LE, Berry JW, Weiss J, Morrison A, Acampora A. Guilt, shame, and depression in clients in recovery from addiction. J. Psychoactive Drugs. 1996;28:125–134. doi: 10.1080/02791072.1996.10524385. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  123. Merisca R, Bybee JS. Guilt, not moral reasoning, relates to volunteerism, prosocial behavior, lowered aggressiveness, and eschewal of racism; Poster presented at Annu. Meet. East. Psychol. Assoc.; Providence, RI. 1994. [Google Scholar]
  124. Miller PA, Eisenberg N. The relation of empathy to aggressive and externalizing/antisocial behavior. Psychol. Bull. 1988;103:324–344. doi: 10.1037/0033-2909.103.3.324. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  125. Miller RS. The nature and severity of self-reported embarrassing circumstances. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 1992;18:190–198. [Google Scholar]
  126. Miller RS. Embarrassment and social behavior. See Tangney&Fischer 1995. 1995a:322–339. [Google Scholar]
  127. Miller RS. On the nature of embarrassability: shyness, social-evaluation, and social skill. J. Personal. 1995b;63:315–339. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-6494.1995.tb00812.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  128. Miller RS. Embarrassment: Poise and Peril in Everyday Life. New York: Guilford; 1996. [Google Scholar]
  129. Mills R. Possible antecedents and developmental implications of shame in young girls. Infant Child Dev. 2003;12:329–349. [Google Scholar]
  130. Mosher DL. The development and multitrait-multimethod matrix analysis of three measures of three aspects of guilt. J. Consult. Clin. Psychol. 1966;30:25–29. [Google Scholar]
  131. Murray C, Waller G. Reported sexual abuse and bulimic psychopathology among non-clinical women: the mediating role of shame. Int. J. Eat. Disord. 2002;32:186–191. doi: 10.1002/eat.10062. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  132. Murray C, Waller G, Legg C. Family dysfunction and bulimia psychopathology: the mediating role of shame. Int. J. Eat. Disord. 2000;28:84–89. doi: 10.1002/(sici)1098-108x(200007)28:1<84::aid-eat10>3.0.co;2-r. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  133. Nathanson DL. Shame and Pride: Affect, Sex, and the Birth of Self. New York: Norton; 1992. [Google Scholar]
  134. Negrao C, Bonanno GA, Noll JG, Putnam FW, Trickett PK. Shame, humiliation, and childhood sexual abuse: distinct contributions and emotional coherence. Child Maltreat. 2005;10(4):350–363. doi: 10.1177/1077559505279366. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  135. Nishith P, Nixon R, Resick P. Resolution of trauma-related guilt following treatment of PTSD in female rape victims: a result of cognitive processing therapy targeting comorbid depression? J. Affect. Disord. 2005;86:259–265. doi: 10.1016/j.jad.2005.02.013. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  136. O’Connor LE, Berry JW, Inaba D, Weiss J. Shame, guilt, and depression in men and women in recovery from addiction. J. Subst. Abuse Treat. 1994;11:503–510. doi: 10.1016/0740-5472(94)90001-9. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  137. O’Connor LE, Berry JW, Weiss J. Interpersonal guilt: the development of a new measure. J. Clin. Psychol. 1997;53:73–89. doi: 10.1002/(sici)1097-4679(199701)53:1<73::aid-jclp10>3.0.co;2-i. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  138. O’Connor LE, Berry JW, Weiss J. Guilt, fear, submission, and empathy in depression. J. Affect. Disord. 2002;71:19–27. doi: 10.1016/s0165-0327(01)00408-6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  139. Orsillo SM, Heimburg RG, Juster HR, Garrett J. Social phobia and PTSD in Vietnam veterans. J. Trauma. Stress. 1996;9:235–252. doi: 10.1007/BF02110658. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  140. Ortony A, Clore GL, Collins A. The Cognitive Structure of Emotions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press; 1988. [Google Scholar]
  141. Paulhus DL, Robins RW, Trzesniewski KH, Tracy JL. Two replicable suppressor situations in personality research. Multivar. Behav. Res. 2004;39:303–328. doi: 10.1207/s15327906mbr3902_7. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  142. Quiles ZN, Bybee J. Chronic and predispositional guilt: relations to mental health, prosocial behavior and religiosity. J. Personal. Assess. 1997;69:104–126. doi: 10.1207/s15327752jpa6901_6. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  143. Resick PA, Nishith P, Weaver TL, Astin MC, Feuer CA. A comparison of cognitive-processing therapy with prolonged exposure and a waiting condition for the treatment of chronic posttraumatic stress disorder in female rape victims. J. Consult. Clin. Psychol. 2002;70(4):867–879. doi: 10.1037//0022-006x.70.4.867. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  144. Rodin J, Silberstein L, Striegel-Moore R. Women and weight: a normative discontent. In: Sonderegger TB, editor. Nebraska Symposium on Motivation. Vol. 32. Lincoln: Univ. Nebraska Press; 1984. pp. 267–307. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  145. Roseman IJ. Appraisal determinants of discrete emotions. Cogn. Emot. 1991;5:161–200. [Google Scholar]
  146. Rozin P, Lowery L, Imada S, Haidt J. The CAD triad hypothesis: a mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity) J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1999;76:574–586. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.76.4.574. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  147. Sabini J, Silver M. In defense of shame: shame in the context of guilt and embarrassment. J. Theory Soc. Behav. 1997;27:1–15. [Google Scholar]
  148. Sanftner JL, Barlow DH, Marschall DE, Tangney JP. The relation of shame and guilt to eating disorders symptomatology. J. Soc. Clin. Psychol. 1995;14:315–324. [Google Scholar]
  149. Schaefer DA. The difference between shame-prone and guilt-prone persons on measures of anxiety, depression and risk of alcohol abuse. Diss. Abstr. Int. B Sci. Eng. 2000;60:2389. [Google Scholar]
  150. Scheff TJ. The shame-rage spiral: a case study of an interminable quarrel. In: Lewis HB, editor. The Role of Shame in Symptom Formation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum; 1987. pp. 109–149. [Google Scholar]
  151. Schmader T, Lickel B. Stigma and shame: emotional responses to the stereotypic actions of one’s ethnic ingroup. In: Levin S, van Laar C, editors. Stigma and Group Inequality: Social Psychological Approaches. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum; 2006. pp. 261–285. [Google Scholar]
  152. Sharkey WF, Stafford L. Responses to embarrassment. Hum. Commun. Res. 1990;17:315–342. [Google Scholar]
  153. Shweder RA, Much NC, Mahapatra M, Park L. The “Big Three” of morality (autonomy, community, divinity) and the “Big Three” explanation of suffering. In: Brandt A, Rozin P, editors. Morality and Health. New York: Routledge; 1997. pp. 119–169. [Google Scholar]
  154. Smith CA, Ellsworth PC. Patterns of cognitive appraisal in emotion. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1985;48:813–838. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  155. Smith RH, Webster JM, Parrot WG, Eyre HL. The role of public exposure in moral and nonmoral shame and guilt. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2002;83:138–159. [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  156. Stuewig J, McCloskey L. The impact of maltreatment on adolescent shame and guilt: psychological routes to depression and delinquency. Child Maltreat. 2005;10:324–336. doi: 10.1177/1077559505279308. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  157. Stuewig J, Tangney JP, Heigel C, Harty L. Re-examining the relationship between shame, guilt, and aggression. 2006 Manuscr. in prep. [Google Scholar]
  158. Swim JK, Miller DL. White guilt: its antecedents and consequences for attitudes toward affirmative action. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 1999;25:500–514. [Google Scholar]
  159. Talbot J, Talbot N, Tu X. Shame-proneness as a diathesis for dissociation in women with histories of childhood sexual abuse. J. Traum. Stress. 2004;17(5):445–448. doi: 10.1023/B:JOTS.0000048959.29766.ae. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  160. Tangney JP. Assessing individual differences in proneness to shame and guilt: development of the Self-Conscious Affect and Attribution Inventory. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1990;59:102–111. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.59.1.102. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  161. Tangney JP. Moral affect: the good, the bad, and the ugly. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1991;61:598–607. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.61.4.598. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  162. Tangney JP. Situational determinants of shame and guilt in young adulthood. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 1992;18:199–206. [Google Scholar]
  163. Tangney JP. Shame and guilt. In: Costello CG, editor. Symptoms of Depression. New York: Wiley; 1993. pp. 161–180. [Google Scholar]
  164. Tangney JP. The mixed legacy of the superego: adaptive and maladaptive aspects of shame and guilt. In: Masling JM, Bornstein RF, editors. Empirical Perspectives on Object Relations Theory. Washington, DC: Am. Psychol. Assoc; 1994. pp. 1–28. [Google Scholar]
  165. Tangney JP. Recent empirical advances in the study of shame and guilt. Am. Behav. Sci. 1995a;38:1132–1145. [Google Scholar]
  166. Tangney JP. Shame and guilt in interpersonal relationships. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995b:114–139. [Google Scholar]
  167. Tangney JP. Conceptual and methodological issues in the assessment of shame and guilt. Behav. Res. Ther. 1996;34:741–754. doi: 10.1016/0005-7967(96)00034-4. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  168. Tangney JP, Burggraf SA, Wagner PE. Shame-proneness, guilt-proneness, and psychological symptoms. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:343–367. [Google Scholar]
  169. Tangney JP, Dearing R. Shame and Guilt. New York: Guilford; 2002. [Google Scholar]
  170. Tangney JP, Fischer KW, editors. Self-Conscious Emotions: The Psychology of Shame, Guilt, Embarrassment, and Pride. New York: Guilford; 1995. [Google Scholar]
  171. Tangney JP, Marschall DE, Rosenberg K, Barlow DH, Wagner PE. Children’s and Adults’ Autobiographical Accounts of Shame, Guilt and Pride Experiences: An Analysis of Situational Determinants and Interpersonal Concerns. Fairfax, VA: George Mason Univ; 1994. Unpubl. manuscr. [Google Scholar]
  172. Tangney JP, Mashek D, Stuewig J. Working at the social-clinical-community-criminology interface: the GMU inmate study. J. Soc. Clin. Psychol. 2006 doi: 10.1521/jscp.2007.26.1.1. In press. [DOI] [PMC free article] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  173. Tangney JP, Miller RS, Flicker L, Barlow DH. Are shame, guilt and embarrassment distinct emotions? J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1996a;70:1256–1269. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.70.6.1256. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  174. Tangney JP, Stuewig J, Mashek D. An emotional-cognitive framework for understanding moral behavior. Fairfax, VA: George Mason Univ.; 2006b. Unpubl. manuscr. [Google Scholar]
  175. Tangney JP, Wagner PE, Burggraf SA, Gramzow R, Fletcher C. Children’s shame-proneness, but not guilt-proneness, is related to emotional and behavioral maladjustment; Poster presented meet. Am. Psychol. Soc.; Washington, DC. 1991. [Google Scholar]
  176. Tangney JP, Wagner PE, Fletcher C, Gramzow R. Shamed into anger? The relation of shame and guilt to anger and self-reported aggression. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1992;62:669–675. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.62.4.669. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  177. Tangney JP, Wagner P, Gramzow R. The Test of Self-Conscious Affect (TOSCA) Fairfax, VA: George Mason Univ; 1989. [Google Scholar]
  178. Tangney JP, Wagner PE, Hill-Barlow D, Marschall DE, Gramzow R. Relation of shame and guilt to constructive versus destructive responses to anger across the lifespan. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 1996b;70:797–809. doi: 10.1037//0022-3514.70.4.797. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  179. Tibbetts SG. Shame and rational choice in offending decisions. Crim. Justice Behav. 1997;24:234–255. [Google Scholar]
  180. Tibbetts SG. Self-conscious emotions and criminal offending. Psychol. Rep. 2003;93:101–126. doi: 10.2466/pr0.2003.93.1.101. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  181. Tomkins SS. Affect, Imagery, Consciousness. Volume 2. The Negative Affects. New York: Springer; 1963. [Google Scholar]
  182. Tracy JL, Robins RW. Putting the self into self-conscious emotions: a theoretical model. Psychol. Inq. 2004a;15:103–125. [Google Scholar]
  183. Tracy JL, Robins RW. Show your pride: evidence for a discrete emotion expression. Psychol. Sci. 2004b;15(3):194–197. doi: 10.1111/j.0956-7976.2004.01503008.x. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  184. Tracy JL, Robins RW. Appraisal antecedents of shame, guilt, and pride: support for a theoretical model. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 2006 doi: 10.1177/0146167206290212. In press. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  185. Wallbott HG, Scherer KR. Cultural determinants in experiencing shame and guilt. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:465–487. [Google Scholar]
  186. Weiss J. How Psychotherapy Works. New York: Guilford; 1993. [Google Scholar]
  187. Weitzman O, Kemeny ME, Fahey JL. HIV-related Shame and Guilt Predict CD4 Decline. 2004 Manuscr. submitted. [Google Scholar]
  188. Wicker FW, Payne GC, Morgan RD. Participant descriptions of guilt and shame. Motiv. Emot. 1983;7:25–39. [Google Scholar]
  189. Widom C, Raphael K, DuMont K. The case for prospective longitudinal studies in child maltreatment research: commentary on Dube, Williamson, Thompson, Felitti and Anda 2004. Child Abuse Neglect. 2004;28:175–722. doi: 10.1016/j.chiabu.2004.03.009. [DOI] [PubMed] [Google Scholar]
  190. Zahn-Waxler C, Robinson J. Empathy and guilt: early origins of feelings of responsibility. See Tangney & Fischer 1995. 1995:143–173. [Google Scholar]
  191. Zebel S, Doojse B, Spears R. It depends on your point of view: implications of perspective-taking and national identification for Dutch collective guilt. In: Branscombe NR, Doosje B, editors. Collective Guilt: International Perspectives. New York: Cambridge Univ. Press; 2004. pp. 148–168. [Google Scholar].”

Article 2 (A2 after this): “The role of emotions in ethics according to six big thinkers

Opinion + AnalysisRelationships
BY The Ethics Centre 16 APR 2021

It’s not easy to provide a clear definition of emotions. Philosophers and psychologists still haven’t agreed on what they are or whether they’re ethically important.

Most of us have lots of emotions and can name a dozen off the top of our heads pretty quickly. But there’s a lot more to understand. Why do they matter? Are we in control of our emotions? Should we prioritise our reason over our emotion?

Let’s take a look at what philosophy has to say.”

 

My response: I too have struggled with what emotions are, how to define them clearly with final decisiveness (not likely to occur), but I have an inescapable idea that emotions are ethically important but that our reasoning takes precedent over them—or should once individuating with an incompatibilist free will and good will operating in the agent at full steam.

It occurred to me that the Divine Couple, the Creators of this world and the next world, are not purely but are primarily and essentially rational Beings, whose immaterial principle and power of conceptualization is explained in such laws and languages as verbal expression and mathematical formulas and proofs.  The Divine Couple are nearly ethically perfect, so their Logos, their Divine Reason, which runs through nature and supernature, the cosmos they created, that requires logical guidance.

Since the Divine Couple, creators of cosmos, imbued their creation with supernatural law and natural law, and this Couple are so morally perfected, then it seems likely that an individuating human being, seeking to emulate these Divine Individuators, would also achieve moral perfection of a small kind by reasoning about moral matters, and acting in accordance with devised moral law.

A2: “Plato: reason rules emotion

For Ancient Greek philosopher Plato, emotion was a core part of our mind. But although it was core, he didn’t think emotions were very useful. He suggested we imagine our mind like a chariot with two horses. One horse is noble and cooperative, the other is wild and uncontrollable.

Plato thought the chariot rider was our reason and the two horses were different kinds of emotions. The noble horse represents our ‘moral emotions’ like righteous anger or empathy. The cranky horse represents more basic passions like rage, lust and hunger. Plato’s ideas set the precedent for Western philosophy in placing reason above and in control of our emotions.”

My response: It seems right generally that the moral agent should place her reason above and in control of her emotions.

A2: “Aristotle: what you feel says something about you

Aristotle had similar ideas and believed the wise, virtuous person would feel the right emotions at the right times. They would be depressed by sad things and angered by injustice. He also believed this appropriate kind of feeling was an important measure of whether you were a good person. He didn’t think you could separate the kind of person you were from the way you felt.

So if you find it funny when someone slips over in a puddle, Aristotle would argue that says something about you. It doesn’t matter whether you then offer them a towel or ask if they’re okay. The amusement you felt in response to their suffering reflects your character. He thought your job is to work hard so instead of laughing at such situations, you feel empathy and concern.”

 

My response: Both Plato and Aristotle urged that the moral person’s reason controls his emotions.

A2: “Hume: emotion rules reason

Scottish philosopher David Hume thought this view was naive. He famously said reason is “the slave of the passions”. By this he meant our emotions lead our reason – we never choose to do anything because reason tells us to. We do it because an emotion pushes us to act. For Hume, reason isn’t the charioteer driving our emotions, it’s more like the wagon being pulled along with no control over where it’s headed. It’s the horses – our emotions – calling the shots.”

My response: Hume is more wrong than right, that reason is the slave of the passions, especially in nonindividuators practicing altruist ethics, and who think very little or at all. As one maverizes and learns intelligent self-control, reason assumes the reins of power if one would be a good person, but, even then, our feelings carry great but not always helpful influence in our choosing and actions undertaken.

A2: “Hume and his friend Adam Smith developed a theory of moral sentiments that used emotion as the basis for their ethical theory. For them, we act virtuously not because our reason tells us it’s the right thing to do, but because doing the right thing feels good. We get a kind of ‘moral pleasure’ from acting well.

Kant: emotion strips our agency

Immanuel Kant thought this whole approach was entirely wrongheaded. He believed emotion had no place in our ethical thinking. For Kant, emotions were pathological – a disease on our thinking. Because we have no control over our emotions, Kant thought allowing them to govern our thinking and action made us ‘automated’, and that it is the only reason that made us autonomous and capable of making truly free decisions.”

My response: I do not regard emotions as pathological, but they run deep and could be heteronomous and automated. I agree with Kant that free will, individualism and rational processes are inextricably bound up with each other.

A2: “Freud: our unconscious drives us

More recent ideas have questioned whether there is such a thing as ‘pure reason’ (a concept Kant named one of his books after). Psychoanalysts like Sigmund Freud encouraged us to see our motivations as driven by unconscious urges and inclinations. More recent work in neuroscience has revealed the role unconscious bias and heuristics play in our beliefs, thinking and decisions.

This might make us wonder whether the idea that reason and emotion are two separate, rival forces is accurate. Another mode of thinking suggests our emotions are part of our reason. They express our judgements about how the world is and how we’d like it to be. Are we passive victims of our emotions? Do we spontaneously ‘explode’ with anger? Or is it something we choose? Our answer will help us determine how we feel about things like ‘crimes of passions’, impulsive decisions and how responsible we are for the feelings of other people.

Carol Gilligan: What is this sexist nonsense?

You may have noticed that all the names on this list so far are men. For psychologist Carol Gilligan, that’s not a coincidence. In her influential work In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development, Gilligan argued that the widespread suspicion of ethical decisions made on the basis of emotion, concern for other people and a desire to maintain relationships was sexist. Most theorists had argued that reason, not emotion, should drive our decisions. Gilligan pointed out that most of the ‘bad’ ways of making decisions (like showing care for certain people or using emotion as a guide) tended to be the ways women reasoned about moral problems. Instead, she argued that a tendency to pay mind to emotions, value care and connection and prioritise relationships were different modes of moral reasoning; not suboptimal ones.

For a long time, reason and emotion have been pitted against one another. Today, we’re starting to understand that, in many ways, emotions and reason are the same. Our emotions are judgements about the world. Our reasoning is informed by our mood, our environment and a range of other factors. Perhaps the question shouldn’t be “should we listen to our emotions?” but instead “how do we develop the right emotional responses at the right time?” That way, we can rely on our emotions as one of many pieces of information we can use to make better decisions.”



 

                                                            D

 

I pulled this article off of the Internet on about 6/24/25, an article by psychologist Rolf Reber. I copied and pasted the article below, and will comment on it:

 

 

 

 

Article 3 (A3 after this): “

 

 

 

Rolf Reber Ph.D.

Critical Feeling

Ethics and Morality

Do Our Feelings Tell Us What Is Right?

The moral outlook most psychologists endorse is simple – and wrong.”

 

My response: So, most psychologists believe that our feelings tell us what is right; wow, I did not know they were emotivists. As an ontological moderate, I suggest that our reasoning tells us what is right more than our feelings tell us what is right, but that we require and should heed input from both sources of input from our consciences and unconscious.

 

 

 

 

There are two main views on morality.

The traditional one is that there are objective moral norms that tell us what is right to do. It came from religion and assumed that God provides us with the rules and virtues a community needs to live together.”

My response: It seems that Reber is equating rational morality with the view that there are objective moral norms, moral realism.”

 

A3: “Later, philosophers replaced theologians as moral authorities but they continued to look for rules and virtues that could objectively determine the appropriate actions in a given situation. Is it right to steal money to buy medication to my sick mother when there is no other means to heal her? Under which circumstances is it right to kill another person, if at all? When do I have the permission to lie to a friend?

The modern view that became popular among psychologists emerged when it became clear that different moral views clash and it is difficult to determine which one holds true. The solution to this conundrum is as simple as it is false.”

My response: If modern psychologists are emotivists pushing ethical relativism and ethical subjectivism or ethical anti-realism, then Reber opines that though moral views clash and its unclear which moral view is the right one, it is simple and false to no longer seeks morally realist solutions on metaethical or any other level of ethics, and he seems moderate and correct in his conclusion.

It would seem that Reber regards ruled-based morality as a form of moral realism.

A3: “According to this view, called “emotivism”, there are no objective moral laws. Each man and woman has to decide themselves what is right. What tells them what is right is their conscience, that is, the feelings that accompany an action. If we are lying to a friend and feel badly, then it is morally not permissible to do so. By contrast, if I am lying and feel well, there is according to this view nothing wrong with my lying. However, recent research revealed that people may feel a “cheater’s high”, that is, they enjoy the success of cheating others.

Although popular with psychologists, philosophers identified a major problem with emotivism, namely, that anything goes – there is no way, from this point of view – to determine whether an action or a person’s life is morally good. If a terrorist like the Norwegian Anders Breivik thinks that killing minors is good, then his act is good, an outcome most people – including psychologists – not only find counterintuitive but also abominable.”

 

This is why some scholars advocate new forms of moral realism, that is, the assumption that moral values are “out there”. Beyond religion and virtue ethics, our communities and cultures set moral norms that serve as mindsets. Moral norms do not arise from within, from our minds. We all have grown up in communities where moral values were given. We learned and internalized them. In this regard, moral realism describes better how people arrive at moral values than emotivism that they somehow come from within.

Do feelings play no role whatsoever in assessing the morality of our behavior?”

My response: Reber is seeking a moral realist ethic which is somewhat objective, though perhaps culturally constructed, not universal to all peoples and cultures, though it is well known, and I hope accepted that there are univseral or objectively moral rules applicable to almost all societies, things like the Golden Rule, not lying, not stealing, not murdering.

And Reber below surely will suggest that feelings do play a role in assessing the morality of our behavior.

 

 

A3: “

 Penitent Petrus (Wikimedia, Open Source)

Source: El Greco: Penitent Petrus (Wikimedia, Open Source)

According to classical rule-based morality, feelings would not play a crucial role. Even in virtue ethics, it remains unclear whether emotions tell us anything informative about the morality of our behavior. However, we know from psychological research that feelings provide information, and that such information might tell us whether our action was right or wrong.

Note the difference to emotivism. In emotivism, our behavior is wrong because we feel bad while the idea from moral realism is that we feel bad because our behavior was wrong, and thus our feeling may signal but not justify that our behavior is wrong.

That means that even if one advocates moral realism and claims that moral values are not constructions of an individual’s mind, some indications signal that people are acting against their own values and the values of their community.”

My response: Reber seems realistic and accurate when he points out that we do feel approval or disapproval of a moral choice, and that this is instantaneous and unforced by the agent. This feeling is informative and sometimes decisive, but it is working in tandem with out lived and adopted objective moral code, and could decline into being the whimsical, unsystematic, and even arbitrary sentiment favored under emotivism.

A3: “First, and almost trivially, most people feel scruples when they do something wrong. If a Sally is not too scrupulous, a bad conscience is a good indicator that she is not acting virtuously even when she uses her feelings to achieve a personally desired outcome – say, to sell a bad car for a good price by not telling the buyer about its deficiencies.

Second, the car selling example is not only about having scruples but also about concealing information. Having the impression that we have to conceal facts that would be relevant in the dealings with another person, we should ask ourselves whether we are acting virtuously. There are some situations where hiding information is appropriate, such as concealing what present I shall bestow my wife on Christmas; but often, hiding information or even providing deceiving information is a sign that we use critical thinking or critical feeling not in the service of values, but as a technique to give us a cutting edge.

Third, feelings may come from the wrong source and therefore lead to the false action. A father who is angry because he lost money in gambling should not let the steam off at his children. Another kind of wrong source may stem from education. When children were made to feel guilty during their upbringing, they may feel guilty in situations where the community at large would consider this feeling as unfounded. Critical feeling attempts at least to detect such erroneous sources in order to align behavior to the values one endorses.”

My response: Reber seems to be some kind of moral moderate, allowing for feelings to guide our moral choices, though we think about our choices rationally, informed by the system of norms which we inherited from society, the community, our parents.

A3: “These first three indicators all pertain to contradictions between thoughts or actions, and feelings; the contradictions lie within our own mind.

There is a fourth indicator that measures the contradiction between our actions and norms of the family, community, or society. Actions and feelings may be in perfect agreement, but the action may be wrong nevertheless. Transgressing norms and values of our group or society may be a sign that we are on the wrong side. Norms have grown from tradition, and we may assume that they have some function.

To summarize, we are brought up with moral norms within our family, community, and culture. These moral norms stem from tradition. Children internalize those moral norms without questioning them and without even knowing that there could be alternatives. Although such norms may be outdated, we should not dismiss them lightly because tradition tells us that they stood the test of time.”

 

 

                                                      E

 

Here is an article I downloaded, copied, and pasted from the Internet on 6/24/25. It is a 2009 article from the Markula Center Of Applied Ethics. Here is the article:

 

 

 

Article 4 (A4 after this): “Ethical Reasoning: Student Guide to a Framework for Thinking Ethically

This document is designed as an introduction to thinking ethically. We all have

an image of our better selves-of how we are when we act ethically or are "at our best."

We probably also have an image of what an ethical community, an ethical business, an

ethical government, or an ethical society should be. Ethics really has to do with all these

levels-acting ethically as individuals, creating ethical organizations and governments,

and making our society as a whole ethical in the way it treats everyone.

What is Ethics?

Simply stated, ethics refers to standards of behavior that tell us how human

beings ought to act in the many situations in which they find themselves-as friends,

parents, children, citizens, businesspeople, teachers, professionals, and so on.”

 

My response: I like Markula’s definition of ethics as referring to the standards of behavior that us how human beings ought to act.

 

A4: “It is helpful to identify what ethics is NOT:

• Ethics is not the same as feelings. Feelings provide important information for

our ethical choices. Some people have highly developed habits that make them feel bad

when they do something wrong, but many people feel good even though they are doing

something wrong. And often our feelings will tell us it is uncomfortable to do the right

thing if it is hard.”

 

My response: The Markula approach to ethics is not emotivism, it is going to be realistic and rule-driven, but there is a place for emotional hunches which may be more pertinent to the agent, more accurate, more insightful, though how this works and how reliable it is varies from person to person, and situation to situation.

 

A4: “

• Ethics is not religion. Many people are not religious, but ethics applies to

everyone. Most religions do advocate high ethical standards but sometimes do not

address all the types of problems we face.

• Ethics is not following the law. A good system of law does incorporate many

ethical standards, but law can deviate from what is ethical. Law can become ethically

corrupt, as some totalitarian regimes have made it. Law can be a function of power

alone and designed to serve the interests of narrow groups. Law may have a difficult

time designing or enforcing standards in some important areas, and may be slow to

address new problems.”

 

My response: It seems that ethics is not religion but it is useful and beneficial if people worship a good deity and seek to behave.

 

Ethics is not following the law unless it is a just law.

 

 

A4: “• Ethics is not following culturally accepted norms. Some cultures are quite

ethical, but others become corrupt - or blind to certain ethical concerns (as the United

States was to slavery before the Civil War). "When in Rome, do as the Romans do" is not

a satisfactory ethical standard.

• Ethics is not science. Social and natural science can provide important data to

help us make better ethical choices. But science alone does not tell us what we ought to

do. Science may provide an explanation for what humans are like. But ethics provides

reasons for how humans ought to act. And just because something is scientifically or

technologically possible, it may not be ethical to do it.”

 

 

 

My response: I do approve of the Markula system in disagreeing that ethics is to be conflated with religion, law, culturally accepted norms, or science.

 

 

 

A4: “Why Identifying Ethical Standards is Hard

There are two fundamental problems in identifying the ethical standards we are

to follow:

1. On what do we base our ethical standards?

2. How do those standards get applied to specific situations we face?

If our ethics are not based on feelings, religion, law, accepted social practice, or science,

what are they based on? Many philosophers and ethicists have helped us answer this

critical question. They have suggested at least five different sources of ethical standards

we should use.”

 

My response: I approve of how Markula lays out the problem of what is ethical and how to apply standards to choices and actions optional and available to the agent.

 

A4: “Five Sources of Ethical Standards

1. The Utilitarian Approach

Some ethicists emphasize that the ethical action is the one that provides the most

good or does the least harm, or, to put it another way, produces the greatest balance of

good over harm. The ethical corporate action, then, is the one that produces the

greatest good and does the least harm for all who are affected-customers, employees,

shareholders, the community, and the environment. Ethical warfare balances the good

achieved in ending terrorism with the harm done to all parties through death, injuries,

and destruction. The utilitarian approach deals with consequences; it tries both to

increase the good done and to reduce the harm done.

2. The Rights Approach

Other philosophers and ethicists suggest that the ethical action is the one that best

protects and respects the moral rights of those affected. This approach starts from the

belief that humans have a dignity based on their human nature per se or on their ability

to choose freely what they do with their lives. On the basis of such dignity, they have a

right to be treated as ends and not merely as means to other ends. The list of moral

rights -including the rights to make one's own choices about what kind of life to lead, to

be told the truth, not to be injured, to a degree of privacy, and so on-is widely debated;

some now argue that non-humans have rights, too. Also, it is often said that rights imply

duties-in particular, the duty to respect others' rights.

3. The Fairness or Justice Approach

Aristotle and other Greek philosophers have contributed the idea that all equals

should be treated equally. Today we use this idea to say that ethical actions treat all

human beings equally-or if unequally, then fairly based on some standard that is

defensible. We pay people more based on their harder work or the greater amount that

they contribute to an organization, and say that is fair. But there is a debate over CEO

salaries that are hundreds of times larger than the pay of others; many ask whether the

huge disparity is based on a defensible standard or whether it is the result of an

imbalance of power and hence is unfair.

4. The Common Good Approach

The Greek philosophers have also contributed the notion that life in community is a

good in itself and our actions should contribute to that life. This approach suggests that

the interlocking relationships of society are the basis of ethical reasoning and that

respect and compassion for all others-especially the vulnerable-are requirements of

such reasoning. This approach also calls attention to the common conditions that are

important to the welfare of everyone. This may be a system of laws, effective police and

fire departments, health care, a public educational system, or even public recreational

areas.

5. The Virtue Approach

A very ancient approach to ethics is that ethical actions ought to be consistent with

certain ideal virtues that provide for the full development of our humanity. These

virtues are dispositions and habits that enable us to act according to the highest

potential of our character and on behalf of values like truth and beauty. Honesty,

courage, compassion, generosity, tolerance, love, fidelity, integrity, fairness, self-

control, and prudence are all examples of virtues. Virtue ethics asks of any action,

"What kind of person will I become if I do this?" or "Is this action consistent with my

acting at my best?"

Putting the Approaches Together

Each of the approaches helps us determine what standards of behavior can be

considered ethical. There are still problems to be solved, however.

The first problem is that we may not agree on the content of some of these specific

approaches. We may not all agree to the same set of human and civil rights.

We may not agree on what constitutes the common good. We may not even

agree on what is a good and what is a harm.

The second problem is that the different approaches may not all answer the question

"What is ethical?" in the same way. Nonetheless, each approach gives us important

information with which to determine what is ethical in a particular circumstance. And

much more often than not, the different approaches do lead to similar answers.”

My response: I like the blending or moderate approach Markula offers to mix together these five sources of ethical standards. What was new to me was Markula’s suggestion that more often than not the different approaches to lead to similar ethical answers.”

 

 

A4: “Making Decisions

Making good ethical decisions requires a trained sensitivity to ethical issues and

a practiced method for exploring the ethical aspects of a decision and weighing the

considerations that should impact our choice of a course of action. Having a method for

ethical decision making is absolutely essential. When practiced regularly, the method

becomes so familiar that we work through it automatically without consulting the

specific steps.

The more novel and difficult the ethical choice we face, the more we need to rely

on discussion and dialogue with others about the dilemma. Only by careful exploration

of the problem, aided by the insights and different perspectives of others, can we make

good ethical choices in such situations.

We have found the following framework for ethical decision making a useful method for

exploring ethical dilemmas and identifying ethical courses of action.

A Framework for Ethical Decision Making

Recognize an Ethical Issue

1. Could this decision or situation be damaging to someone or to some group? Does this

decision involve a choice between a good and bad alternative, or perhaps

between two "goods" or between two "bads"?

2. Is this issue about more than what is legal or what is most efficient? If so, how?

Get the Facts

3. What are the relevant facts of the case? What facts are not known? Can I learn more

about the situation? Do I know enough to make a decision?

4. What individuals and groups have an important stake in the outcome? Are some

concerns more important? Why?

5. What are the options for acting? Have all the relevant persons and groups been

consulted? Have I identified creative options?

Evaluate Alternative Actions

6. Evaluate the options by asking the following questions:

 Which option will produce the most good and do the least harm? (The Utilitarian

Approach)

 Which option best respects the rights of all who have a stake? (The Rights

Approach)

 Which option treats people equally or proportionately? (The Justice Approach)

 Which option best serves the community as a whole, not just some members?

(The Common Good Approach)

 Which option leads me to act as the sort of person I want to be? (The Virtue

Approach)

Make a Decision and Test It

7. Considering all these approaches, which option best addresses the situation?

8. If I told someone I respect-or told a television audience-which option I have

chosen, what would they say?

Act and Reflect on the Outcome

9. How can my decision be implemented with the greatest care and attention to

the concerns of all stakeholders?

10. How did my decision turn out and what have I learned from this specific

situation?

This framework for thinking ethically is the product of dialogue and debate at the Markkula Center for Applied Ethics at Santa Clara

University. Primary contributors include Manuel Velasquez, Dennis Moberg, Michael J. Meyer, Thomas Shanks, Margaret R. McLean,

David DeCosse, Claire André, and Kirk O. Hanson. It was last revised in May 2009. Santa Clara College, Markula Center for Applied

Ethics http://www.scu.edu/ethics/practicing/decision/framework

 

My response: This section of the Markula approach, of ethically applying one’s blended approach to ethics is sound and useful for any moral agent, not just children and students.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

                                                           F

 

Jordan Peterson has never described himself as an emotivist, that I know of, but he clearly is promoting altruism, collectivism, utilitarianism, and perhaps ethical irrationalism or existentialism. The ethical agent must be humble, selfless, live a life of service to others and beware worshiping his own intellect, ego and implicitly his individual concerns.

 

I refute his moral solutions, but his video above studied triggered in me a need to lay out if intellect or sentiment was to guide our moral decisions.

 

Article 5 below copied and pasted on about 6/24/25 from the Internet. Here it is:

 

 

Article 5 (A5 after this): “The Role of Emotions in Moral Decision Making: How Do Emotions Influence Our Moral Decisions?

A silhouette of a person with a cloud of thought

Description automatically generated

Morality is a complex concept that involves making decisions that reflect our values, beliefs, and principles. In the process of making moral decisions, emotions play a crucial role. Emotions shape our experiences and shape the way we perceive the world around us. They impact our moral judgments, influence our decision-making processes, and help us to make ethical choices.

How Do Emotions Influence Our Moral Decision Making?

Emotions can have a powerful effect on our moral decision-making processes. When we experience strong emotions, such as empathy or anger, they can influence how we perceive a situation, and shape our judgments about what is right or wrong. Emotions can act as a guide to our moral sense, helping us to recognize when something is morally wrong, and pushing us to take action to address the issue.

According to various studies, emotions have a significant impact on our moral decision-making processes. For instance, a study by Greene and colleagues (2001) found that participants who were shown images that elicited strong emotional reactions made faster and more emotional judgments about whether a particular action was morally acceptable or not. Similarly, a study by Valdesolo and DeSteno (2006) suggested that emotions such as gratitude and empathy could increase altruistic behavior, leading people to make more moral decisions in social dilemmas.

Emotions can also influence our perception of the intentions of others. For instance, if we feel angry, we may be more likely to attribute negative intentions to others, which can influence our moral assessments. On the other hand, if we feel empathy, we may be more likely to believe that others have good intentions and to judge their behavior more favorably.”

My response: Emotions as promoted in Article 5 are overstated as a priority for making moral decisions, but our feelings will be heard, and should be heard, even if our reasoning overpowers our sentiment about what we are experiencing.

A5: “Can We Make Moral Decisions Without Emotions?

It is difficult to make moral decisions without emotions, as emotions are an integral part of our moral sense. While rational considerations like rules, norms, and principles play a critical role in moral decision-making, emotions provide a sense of depth and urgency to those decisions. Emotions help us to connect more deeply with the moral problem at hand, to understand how it may affect other people, and to motivate us to take action.:”

My response: I like the author’s stressing that emotional reaction to a problem can provide a sense of depth and urgency to the problem under consideration.

I also like the suggestion from the author that our moral sense is part emotion and likely part rational intuition.

A5: “Furthermore, emotions play a critical role in situations where we are confronted with moral dilemmas, where we have to choose between two conflicting moral principles. In such cases, emotions can help us to prioritize our values and to make decisions that are consistent with our overall moral commitments.

For example, consider the case of the famous American author, Harriet Beecher Stowe, who wrote the abolitionist novel, Uncle Tom’s Cabin. Stowe strongly opposed slavery and was deeply moved by the emotional stories of ex-slaves she encountered. Her emotional response to the moral dilemma of slavery motivated her to write Uncle Tom’s Cabin and played an instrumental role in the abolitionist movement in the United States. Her moral decision to take action against slavery was a product of her emotional response to the injustice of the situation.

Empathy and Moral Decision Making

Empathy is one of the most powerful emotions that can influence our moral decision-making processes. Empathy involves putting ourselves in someone else’s shoes, feeling what they feel, and understanding their experiences. Empathy can help us to see the world from different perspectives and to understand the impact of our decisions on others.

Research suggests that empathy can lead to better moral decision making, as it prompts us to consider how our decisions affect others. For example, a study by Batson and colleagues (1997) found that participants who were induced to feel empathy for a person in need were more likely to help that person, even when it required personal sacrifice.

Empathy can play a critical role in moral decision-making in different contexts. For instance, consider the case of doctors who have to make end-of-life decisions for their patients. Empathy can help doctors to understand their patients’ experiences, to see things from their patients’ perspectives, and to make decisions that are consistent with their patients’ values and preferences.

References

  • Batson, C. D., Dyck, J. L., Ecklund, E. L., Lehman, D. R., Wagner, H. L., & Toth, E. L. (1986). Empathic joy and the empathy-altruism hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52(4), 781-790.
  • Greene, J. D., Sommerville, R. B., Nystrom, L. E., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293(5537), 2105-2108.
  • Valdesolo, P., & DeSteno, D. (2006). Manipulations of emotional context shape moral judgment. Psychological Science, 17(6), 476-477.”

 

 

 

G

 

 

 

 

 

 

Is Morality Based on Emotions or Reason?

A new book takes aim at those who claim moral impulses are rooted in emotional ones.

Jill Suttie

Perhaps you’ve heard of the Trolley Problem. It’s a dilemma used to study moral thinking, and it goes something like this: If you see an out of control trolley bearing down on five innocent people, will you throw a switch to divert the train to a track where just one person is standing? Or, given the same dangerous runaway trolley, will you throw a large person off of a bridge in order to impede the trolley’s progress and save five lives?

A book cover with text

Description automatically generatedOxford University Press, 2015, 217 pages

Most of us would say “yes” to the first question and “no” to the second, even though there is the same “body count” involved. Psychologists and neuroscientists like Jonathan Haidt and Joshua Greene have used hypothetical moral dilemmas like this one to study some of the unconscious processes that go into moral decision-making. Their research has led to some fascinating findings about how emotions and environmental cues work together to influence our moral choices.

But in a new book, The Power of Ideals: The Real Story of Moral Choice, renowned moral development experts William Damon and Anne Colby take aim at views that claim morality is largely driven by emotions or is the result of environmental influences beyond our control. Instead, the authors argue, morality is dependent on conscious, deliberate processes—like reflection, learning, and aspiration—and any model of moral development that discounts these is both flawed and disheartening.”

My response: No, morality is not only or mostly driven by emotions—at least it should not be solely or mostly driven by emotions, but our conscious, deliberate, rational processes must be engaged and primary.

A6: “‘Moral psychologies that try only to demonstrate the limitations of everyday morality but ignore people’s authentic search for truth and goodness capture only the weakest elements in our nature,” they write.

According to Damon and Colby, we should not be looking to neuroscience to study morality, because findings from such studies are hard to interpret—in part because they are often conducted on limited populations, like college students, and focus on dilemmas, like the trolley problem, that one is unlikely to face in real life. Instead, they point to other research focused on real-life moral development, like that of Martin Hoffman at New York University. Hoffman has found that empathy in children develops in conjunction with increased “moral cognition”—for example, an understanding that what’s fair in one circumstance may not be fair in another. Damon and Colby believe that research like his illustrates how cognitions shape our emotional responses, which in turn can impact “unconscious” moral choices.

“Once [people] acquire new moral insights, even provisionally, these become background assumptions that influence their moral perceptions, their interpretations, and their choices without the need to deliberate about them anew in each instance,” they write.”

My response: It seems likely that our prior cognitions do influence our unconscious moral choices, and underpin “spontaneous, unrehearsed” emotional moral choice.

A6: “There is much to be learned by studying historical moral exemplars, too, according to Damon and Colby, and their book focuses mostly on the lives of moral exemplars like Eleanor Roosevelt and Nelson Mandela. The authors identify three character traits that they believe particularly influence moral character and can be consciously cultivated: truthfulness, humility, and faith.”

My response: These psychologists are onto something when they suggest that character traits can be cultivated until they become natural, and this reminds of a Dennis Prager excerpt I observed and wrote down off the Internet the other day: “You feel how you act. Don’t act how you feel. Let your action induce the feelings”.

We need be hesitant to just make moral, spontaneous, natural moral choices, spurred by our feelings at the moment though some hunches are spot on. It may be more useful to identify character traits that are noble and desirable, and practice those traits until they are you, so you act nobly and that is how you feel. Prager wants people to learn to be moral by conscious effort, and to role play being good until we become good. This might fit well with virtue ethics, and it certainly seems to fit what Suttie is pushing. Prager exhorts us that feeling by itself should not guide moral choice, that we need rational, careful choice selections, grounded in being a moral adult, following some ethical standard.

A6: “In their definition, truthfulness means more than being honest in everyday encounters; it also means using deep self-reflection and being open to new ideas and experiences. They point to the work of Albert Bandura, who found that people sometimes rationalize immoral behavior by using tactics like denial or distortion, dehumanizing victims, or assuming someone else is responsible to for doing the right thing. Deep self-reflection and openness, they argue, can be an antidote to these and other self-deception tactics, and helps moral exemplars to find deeper truths and to take moral action. This is all clearly demonstrated by the life of Nelson Mandela, who used his time in prison to reflect on larger truths and to find a way to forgive his tormentors.

The importance of truthfulness seems reasonably clear; but when Damon and Colby move on to articulate a definition of humility, they seem to get somewhat bogged down. Humility, they write, is hard to measure, as truly humble people would not claim to be humble. In addition, not all psychologists even agree that humility is a virtue worth pursuing, in part because it may involve self-deprecation. And certainly the moral exemplars noted in the book would not be considered “meek” or “subservient”—both words used synonymously with humility.

In the end, the authors define humility as “a sense of perspective on oneself and one’s abilities and achievement, a willingness to admit mistakes and limitations, open-mindedness and openness to new ideas, an appreciation of the many different kinds of contribution people from all backgrounds can make to the world and a relative absence of self-seeking as a driving motive.” To which I thought: Huh? This doesn’t sound like humility to me—more like a combo platter of other, worthy psychological constructs.

I wish they’d bypassed this all and gotten straight to the point: moral exemplars aren’t interested in self-aggrandizement. In fact, they often don’t see themselves as special. Their humbleness tends to separate them from the fanatics of the world—those who might also believe that they’re in touch with “truth,” but whom none of us would consider moral exemplars.”

My response: Damon and Colby’s characterization of humility seems more compatible with healthy self-pride which is not inflated, puffed up nor delusional. I want people to be proud, but not braggarts, a sign of insecurity,

A6: “And then there’s the unfortunate use of the word “faith.” Damon and Colby try to back off from its religious undertones by writing things like, “Faith means believing in something” and by arguing that even scientists have faith of a sort. But this clarifies little and obscures what the authors are really getting at—that many moral exemplars are guided by their personal belief in a moral universe (often, but not always, connected to religious beliefs) and have a strong sense of purpose in their lives that helps them transcend adversity. Why use the word “faith” at all?

In fact, this whole section of the book seemed ungrounded to me. Certainly, there was little reference to science. Yet, Damon and Colby are excellent writers and giants in the field of moral development. For these reasons alone the book is well worth reading. Stories of moral exemplars and what their lives have to tell us are always uplifting and inspiring.

And even with my quibbles, the book provides ample food for thought—most notably, the importance of self-reflection and role-modeling in encouraging future moral exemplars. If we want our kids to know right from wrong, we must show them that truthfulness is a virtue worth cultivating, that learning and personal growth are more important than achievement, that doing for others rather than self-aggrandizement leads to long term happiness, and that transcending adversity is easier if one lives a principled life.

Fortunately, each of these pathways to moral character can be approached consciously—without having to imagine throwing anyone off of a bridge.”

 

 

 

                                                          H

 

In this Internet excerpt, it seems that reasoning will help us capture moral facts about people and the world, and that our emotions can inform and reinforce decisions logically reached, and choices selected.

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Article 7 (A7 after this): “Are there moral facts based on emotion?

·       Controversies about the comparative roles played by reasoning and emotion in moral judgment have important implications for the nature of moral knowledge. Some sentimentalists suggest that there are no moral facts to be known, for ethics is ultimately a matter of merely having or expressing one’s feelings.”

My response: I am a moral realist more than I am a moral anti-realist so of course I assume that there are knowable moral facts which we can glean, and this will be critical input into how we make moral decisions.

 

 

 

 

 

                                                               I

 

 

 

 

 

It is my sense that our reasoning can move us to chose and act, for it is not only our emotions that triggers our will to act.

 

Article 8 (A8 after this): “

 

 

Moral Reasoning and Emotion - PhilArchive

 

 

What is moral reasoning?

Is morality driven by emotions?

·       But in a new book, The Power of Ideals: The Real Story of Moral Choice, renowned moral development experts William Damon and Anne Colby take aim at views that claim morality is largely driven by emotions or is the result of environmental influences beyond our control.

 

 

 

 

  • · 

o   Philosopher David Hume claims that morality is based more on perceptions than on logical reasoning. [6] This means that people's morality is based more on their emotions and feelings than on a logical analysis of any given situation.

en.wikipedia.org › wiki › Moral_reasoning.”

My response: If our moral choice is one which we have made before, and our quick assessment of the perceived situation is habitually encountered, then we likely will act based on how we feel about what we have just now perceived.

 

If the moral problem encountered is new, unique, or complex, so we in response are unsur how to act, then we mght need a logical analysis of the pros and cons of the situation.

A8: “Moral reasoning - Wikipedia

·  greatergood.berkeley.edu › article › itemIs Morality Based on Emotions or Reason? - Greater Good

Jun 10, 2015 · But in a new book, The Power of Ideals: The Real Story of Moral Choice, renowned moral development experts William Damon and Anne Colby take aim at views that claim morality is largely driven by emotions or is the result of environmental influences beyond our control.

·  open.library.okstate.edu › introphilosophy › chapterReason and Emotion in the Moral Life – Philosophical Thought

My response: Here is an article from open library just above by Scott O’Leary: “

 

 

                              J

 

Article 9 (A9 after this): “Reason and Emotion in the Moral Life

Scott O'Leary

Scott O’Leary received his Ph.D and M.A. in philosophy from Fordham University and his undergraduate degree in philosophy and history from Boston College. He is currently Director of the Honors and Scholars Village at North Carolina State University. Previously, he was an Associate Professor of Philosophy and the Honors Director at the University of Saint Mary (Kansas). Dr. O’Leary’s work focuses on human lived experience and examines the way emotional experience frames consciousness and decision-making. This has led to interests in food ethics and human-technology relations. His work has been published in The American Philosophy Quarterly, Balkan Journal of Philosophy, and Elements, and he received a Templeton Foundation Cluster Grant to create an international working group studying emotion and religious experience. Beyond his academic interests, he spends his free time teaching yoga and mindfulness, herding his cats, and learning about music from his partner, who is a classical pianist.

It may seem puzzling that given the numerous debates in philosophy over the justification of different ethical theories, moral experience often seems to disappear.  In reality, this is less of an omission and more a question of focus. Many canonical moral philosophers like Aristotle, the Stoics, Hume, Kant, Bentham, and Mill have much to say about the motivations, reasoning, and development of moral agents.

Topics like these are the task of the area of philosophy called moral psychology. Many of the central questions in moral psychology require clarifying the roles reason and emotion play in moral experience.  These questions involve three interrelated topics: moral motivation, judgment, and development.

Moral Motivation

Philosophical ethics often places reason at the center of ethical life and views emotion at odds with reason or a source of error.  David Hume comments upon this picture of Western moral philosophy:

 

“Nothing is more usual in philosophy, and even in common life, than to talk of the combat of passion and reason, to give the preference to reason, and assert that men are only so far virtuous as they conform themselves to its dictates. Every rational creature, it is said, is obliged to regulate his actions by reason…” (Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, Part III, Section III: Of the Influencing Motives of the Will.”)

Hume challenges this priority of reason over emotion.  While reason seems central to moral life, emotions are what actually “move us”.  Just as fear leads to fight or flight, indignation can lead us to rectify injustice, anger to correct an offense, or shame to avoid wrongdoing.  Hume argues further that not only can passions motivate action, but reason is impotent and cannot motivate action:

“Abstract or demonstrative reasoning, therefore, never influences any of our actions, but only as it directs our judgment concerning causes and effects….We speak not strictly and philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and of reason. Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them.”  (Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, Part III, Section III: Of the Influencing Motives of the Will.”)”

My response: It could be that our emotions conflict with our moral reasoning or lead to error, but a moderate, rounded, integrated moral motivation if to listen to our feelings and thoughts about actions before we choose a course of action—if time allows.

A9: “O’Leary: “Inspired by Hume, several scholars have argued for a Humean Theory of all motivation, including moral motivation (Smith, 1998).  On this account, human actions are caused by a belief-desire pair.  The belief component, such as “I believe stealing from the store is wrong” leads to the action of resisting the temptation to steal if I also have the desire “to not harm the business owner”Similarly, my sympathy to “help Kevin” combined with the belief “he needs money to pay his bills” is what prompts me to lend him money to make ends meet.

Others challenge this emotion-based theory of moral motivation, most famously Immanuel Kant.  In the Grounding for the Metaphysics for Morals, Kant argues that when we act “for the sake of duty”, we can be motivated by reason.  Kant makes the stronger claim that when we act based on practical reason and not from inclination – his term for desires and emotions – this shows the motive of duty most clearly.  Let’s modify the example above.  Suppose I cannot feel any sympathy to help Kevin, but loan him money anyway because it’s the right thing to do. Kant argues this shows that action can be motivated by practical reason alone.””

My response: Human the emotivist vehemently disagrees with Kant the moral rationalist, but we can be motivated by both and are, and often they may be difficult to differentiate and separate from each other, for every choice, every act may be spontaneous, rationally intuited, logically concluded, or performed from rote moral habit.

Our desires and emotions may move us, but our higher values may guide us to choose in contrast to what we desire or feel.

A9: “I like that Kant counters Hume by arguing that we can be motivated by our practical reason if we act for the sake of duty, not from inclination (desires or emotions),

O’Leary: “Suppose that, when no longer moved by any inclination, he tears himself out of this deadly insensibility and does the action without any inclination for the sake of duty alone; then for the first time his action has its genuine moral worth. [G398].”

What Kant calls genuine moral worth is doing an action because we believe it is the right thing, not because certain feelings motivate us to act.  If ethics is to be universal, then we have to have a source of motivation that is itself universal, and this Kant identifies with the will – that is, practical reason.  Since desires and emotions are subject to each of our own psychological histories, they are too variable and unstable to morally motivate.

This presents two perspectives on moral motivation based on different roles assigned to emotion compared to that of reason.  Hume’s view aligns with our basic intuitions about the motivating capacity of emotion. Kant’s view points to the contingency of emotional life and gains plausibility when we examine the role of emotion and reason in moral judgment.

Moral Judgment

A widespread view in popular culture suggests emotions distort our judgment (see Disney’s “Emotion and Reason” linked below).  Characters like Data and Spock in Star Trek are shown judging situations more clearly and objectively than others because they are unclouded by emotion.  This position is put forward by Stoic philosophers who argued that emotions were “excessive impulses which are disobedient to reason” (Arius Didymus, 65A).  Kant’s ethics also often appear hostile to emotion and desire, separating these two sources of inclination from reason.  Given such critical views of emotion, it may seem surprising that Aristotle places emotion at the center of the virtuous life:

“For instance, both fear and confidence and appetite and anger and pity and in general pleasure and pain may be felt both too much and too little, and in both cases not well; but to feel them at the right times, with reference to the right objects, towards the right people, with the right motive, and in the right way…[that] is characteristic of virtue.”(Book VI Nicomachean Ethics, emphasis added)

Rather than emotions distorting judgment, Aristotle argues that to be virtuous, one must feel emotions at the right times, toward the right object, for the right reason and in the right way.  The courageous person is not fearless, but rather feels the appropriate amount of fear.  In many situations, virtue requires us to feel fear and to feel unafraid is to be rash, falling short of the mark of virtue.”

My response: It could be that we want to follow Aristotle ethical moderation to find generally the mean between two emotional contraries, but we might also need to balance between two rational considerations which could form a false dichotomy for us.

A9: “Both positions can be supported by the empirical literature on moral judgment.  For instance, the phenomenon of emotional priming suggests seemingly insignificant emotional cues may affect how harsh or lenient we judge moral failures in others.  In an experiment with subjects playing the role of a sentencing judge, people judged crimes more harshly when sitting at messy and cluttered desks (Schnall, Haidt, et al 2008).  A similar phenomenon has been observed in other settings such as parole hearings occurring before a judge has lunch.  Should crimes or parole hearings be judged differently just because the judge was hungry, frustrated, or sat at a messy desk?  If this is emotion’s role in moral judgment, then the Stoics position seems correct.

Other studies show emotions provide a crucial role in determining salience and solving what’s called “the frame problem” in philosophy and artificial intelligence research.  Humans constantly and intuitively filter many sources of information.  Setting up an AI algorithm or robot – such as a bomb defusing robot – to do the same is extremely difficult, if not impossible.  How do we filter and determine what is salient in a situation?

Recent studies have shown that our emotional experience provides just such a role (Faucher and Tappolet 2002).  As Dylan Evans summarizes in Emotion: The Science of Sentiment, “[e]motions are often blamed for distracting us….[but] emotions distract us from one thought only in order to make us pay attention to another,” (Evans 2002, p. 114).  Therefore, while the effects of emotion in moral experience may be contested, research suggests that emotions significantly impact our moral judgments and ought to be incorporated into theories of moral judgment.”

My response: Our feelings do impact our moral judgments and should be incorporated into our theory of moral judgment.

A9: “Moral Development

In this final section, we will examine the relationship of emotion and reason in moral development. Each of us should be concerned about the development of our moral character from children to adults and from those who waiver in their ethical commitments to those who remain steadfast.  Rather than pose ways past thinkers or contemporary research might answer these questions, we can examine why these positions in moral psychology are so important for our understanding of the good life itself.

According to Aristotle, to feel the right emotions in the right way is “characteristic of virtue.”   The virtuous person is one whose moral development includes the cultivation of the right emotional sensitivity and feels the right emotions.  For Kant, what is essential is to do the right thing for the right reason, and whether emotions coincide with this or not is generally irrelevant.  In both Bentham and Mill’s accounts of Utilitarianism, the value of emotional experience depends solely on whether emotions promote utility or not.

Such diversity in positions reflects different views on what emotions are and different conceptions of morality itself. For Aristotle, emotions provide important information about ourselves and the world and so their cultivation is an important part of moral development.  One is not fully virtuous if one’s emotions and feelings do not align with one’s reasoning and beliefs.  Thus Kant’s unsympathetic benefactor does the right thing but falls short of virtue because there is a conflict between his action and his feelings.

Is it too demanding to think that our motivations, moral judgments, and feelings will always or typically align?  Does that require a degree of control over early stages of moral development that we in fact do not possess?  To what degree should the cultivation of our own moral character and how we raise our children be centered in our emotional life?  The answer to these questions remains contested; what is not contested is the need to study the relation between emotion and reason in moral experience.

Additional Resources

Cooper, John. “The Emotional Life of the Wise,” Southern Journal of Philosophy, 43(S1); 176-218 (2005).*”

 

My response: I do not know if it is desirable or possible for our emotions and reasons can alight with our motivations and moral judgements, but it is worth investigating.

 

 

                                                            K—Article 10
 

A10: “TCC Foundation logo

Previous/next navigation

Previous: Aristotelian Virtue Ethics

Next: Virtue

 

 

 

Philosophical ethics often places reason at the center of ethical life and views emotion at odds with reason or a source of error. David Hume comments upon this picture of Western moral philosophy: Hume challenges this priority of reason over emotion. While reason seems central to moral life, emotions are what actually “move us”. Just as fear leads...

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

                                                               L

 

Here is an article on moral rationalism which should give a clear picture of the one side of the story, that reason is primary in ethical choosing.

 

 

Article 11 (A11 after this): “What is Moral Rationalism? (Principles, Theory, Examples)

What Is Moral RationalismWhat Is Moral Rationalism

Can morality be based purely on reason? Moral rationalism argues that it can. This philosophy claims that moral truths are objective and can be discovered through logic and reasoning alone. It rejects the idea that morality is based on emotions, social customs, or religious beliefs.”

 

My response: My intuition is that morality is not and should not be based purely on reason, but it primarily should be so based. Moral truths are mostly objective, and yet they are somewhat subjective. Still, logic and reasoning are our best and most productive epistemic tools for uncovering and arriving at moral truths.

There is no doubt that subjective, skeptical, and relativistic considerations influence our moral judgment, that morals are grounded in emotion, social customs, and religious beliefs, is somewhat true and applicable.

A11: “Thinkers like Kant, Plato, and Spinoza have defended this view in different ways. They believe that rational principles guide ethical behavior. Moral rationalism provides a structured approach to ethics, but it also faces criticism. Some argue it ignores human emotions or cultural differences. Understanding this theory helps clarify how reason shapes moral decision-making.”

My response: Moral rationalism argues that morality can be based purely on reason, but it cannot. Morality can be primarily based on reason, but morality receives needed input from emotions, social customs and religious believes, subjective considerations. Jordan Peterson is mostly wrong but not entirely: cultural differences and human emotions must be factored in as contextually relevant.

A11: “Introduction to Moral Rationalism

What is Moral Rationalism?

Moral rationalism is the view that moral truths are known through reason alone. It holds that ethical principles exist independently of human emotions, cultural norms, or divine commands. According to this theory, moral knowledge is not based on experience or intuition but on logical deduction. This makes it similar to mathematical reasoning—just as we discover mathematical truths through rational thought, we uncover moral truths through reasoning.

This approach contrasts with moral sentimentalism, which argues that emotions shape our sense of right and wrong. Moral rationalists believe that ethical rules must be objective, universal, and logically consistent. They argue that moral duties can be understood through careful reasoning rather than feelings or traditions.”

My response: I as an ethical and ontological moderate will blend these two paragraphs above together, and it could be that both good people and evil people are primarily moral sentitmentalists or moral rationalists, in their moral choices.

A11: “Key Philosophers in Moral Rationalism

Several philosophers have shaped moral rationalism. One of the most influential is Immanuel Kant (1724–1804), who argued that moral obligations are derived from reason alone. His Categorical Imperative states that an action is moral if it can be universally applied.

Plato (427–347 BCE) also contributed to this idea. He believed that moral truths exist in an abstract, rational world of Forms, accessible through reason. Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) approached ethics through a geometric method, insisting that moral laws follow from logical necessity. Other thinkers, like René Descartes and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, also supported the idea that moral knowledge comes from rational reflection rather than sensory experience.”

My response: It would seem that moral knowledge comes mostly from a priori and a posteriori rational sources but that our decisions are also informed and directed from internal or a priori sentimental sources as well as from our reacting to what we feel about what we experience in the external world, the a posteriori source of what we feel we choose and act upon.

A11: “Core Principles of Moral Rationalism

#1. Morality Is Grounded in Reason

Moral rationalism asserts that reason is the foundation of morality. Ethical principles are not based on emotions, instincts, or social customs but on logical analysis. Philosophers like Immanuel Kant argue that moral laws must be derived from pure reason, independent of personal desires or external influences.

This means that moral truths are objective and discoverable through rational thought. Just as mathematics follows logical principles, moral reasoning follows strict, universal rules. Rationalists believe that ethical decisions must be justified by reason rather than subjective feelings or arbitrary traditions. This ensures consistency in moral judgments.

#2. Moral Truths Are Objective and Universal

Moral rationalists claim that ethical truths apply to all people at all times. If a moral principle is valid, it must hold regardless of personal beliefs or cultural differences. Kant’s moral philosophy is a prime example—he argues that moral laws must be universal, meaning they apply to everyone in similar situations.

This principle contrasts with moral relativism, which suggests that morality depends on cultural or individual perspectives. Rationalists reject this view, insisting that right and wrong are not subjective. Moral principles are discovered, not invented, through logical reasoning and objective analysis.

#3. Rational Agents Are Morally Accountable

Moral responsibility requires rationality. If morality is based on reason, then only rational beings can be held accountable for their actions. Kant argues that moral obligations apply to individuals precisely because they have the capacity for reasoned decision-making.

This principle excludes animals and individuals lacking rational faculties from full moral responsibility. However, it also strengthens the case for human moral duties. Since people can understand ethical principles, they are obligated to follow them. Ignorance or emotional impulses do not justify immoral actions when reason provides clear moral guidance.

#4. Ethical Judgments Must Be Logically Consistent

A moral principle cannot contradict itself. If a rule applies in one case, it must apply in all similar cases. Rationalists emphasize the need for consistency in ethical decision-making. For example, if lying is considered wrong, it must be wrong in every relevant situation, without exceptions based on convenience.

Kant’s Categorical Imperative reinforces this idea, stating that one should act only on maxims that could be universal laws. This prevents moral contradictions and ensures fairness in ethical reasoning. A rational moral system demands that principles be applied consistently, without self-serving exceptions.

#5. Moral Duties Can Be Discovered Through Rational Reflection

Moral rationalists argue that ethical obligations are not arbitrary but logically necessary. Through careful reasoning, individuals can determine their moral duties without relying on emotions or external authorities. Kant believed that rational beings, by thinking critically, could recognize their ethical responsibilities.

For example, reason tells us that promising something and then breaking the promise contradicts itself. This logical contradiction reveals that honesty is a moral duty. Rational reflection allows individuals to evaluate actions based on universal moral laws rather than personal preferences or societal pressures.

#6. Emotions Should Not Override Moral Reasoning

Moral rationalism does not deny emotions but insists they should not dictate ethical decisions. Feelings can be unreliable and lead to biased or impulsive choices. A rational approach to ethics ensures that moral judgments are based on reason rather than fluctuating emotions.

For instance, anger might make someone seek revenge, but rational moral analysis would show that revenge is unjust. Kant argued that moral duties must be followed even when they conflict with personal feelings. Rationalists maintain that emotions can influence moral awareness but should never replace logical ethical reasoning.

#7. Autonomy Is Central to Moral Agency

Moral rationalism emphasizes autonomy—the ability to act according to reason rather than external pressure. Kant believed that true morality comes from acting freely based on rational principles, not from following authority, customs, or emotions.

This principle means that moral agents must think for themselves and determine what is right through logical reasoning. It also implies that morality requires free will. If someone is forced to act in a certain way, their action lacks moral worth. Only when individuals choose ethical actions through reason can they be truly moral.

#8. Universalizability Is a Test for Moral Principles

A moral principle must be applicable to all people in similar circumstances. If a rule cannot be consistently followed by everyone, it fails as a moral law. This is a core idea in Kant’s philosophy—he argued that before acting, one should ask, “What if everyone did this?”

For example, if stealing were universally accepted, trust in society would collapse. Rationalists use this test to separate legitimate moral duties from self-serving justifications. Universalizability ensures that morality is based on principles that apply equally to all rational beings, preventing ethical double standards.

Examples of Moral Rationalism

#1. Kant’s Categorical Imperative

Immanuel Kant’s Categorical Imperative is a prime example of moral rationalism. He argued that moral rules must be universally applicable and derived from pure reason. A key test of morality is whether an action can be made into a universal law without contradiction. If a rule cannot apply to everyone, it is not truly moral.

For example, lying cannot be moral because if everyone lied, trust would collapse. Kant also emphasized that people should never be treated as mere means to an end. His ethical system prioritizes reason over emotions, ensuring logical consistency in moral decisions.

#2. Plato’s Theory of the Good

Plato believed that moral truths exist independently of human perception. He argued that the highest moral good is found in the Form of the Good, an abstract and rational concept accessible only through reason. Moral knowledge, according to Plato, is not learned through experience but discovered through intellectual inquiry.

In The Republic, he presents the Allegory of the Cave, illustrating that most people see only shadows of reality. Philosophers, through reason, grasp the true nature of morality. Plato’s theory establishes moral rationalism by insisting that ethical understanding depends on rational contemplation, not emotions or social conventions.

#3. Spinoza’s Ethics Based on Geometric Reasoning

Baruch Spinoza applied a mathematical structure to ethics, demonstrating how moral principles follow from reason alone. In Ethics, he used geometric proofs to establish that human flourishing results from rational understanding. He argued that emotions often cloud moral judgment, leading to irrational actions.

Spinoza claimed that true happiness comes from aligning one’s life with rational principles. He rejected free will in the traditional sense, believing that understanding necessity leads to ethical behavior. His system provides a rational foundation for morality, where ethical knowledge emerges from logical deductions rather than subjective experiences.”

 

My response: I admire the author of the above article for his clear, cogent presentation of the 8 ways that moral reasoning needs to work. In the main, I concluded that moral reasoning more than moral feeling will motivate us to reach the right decision most of the time, and that felt reaction to phenomena inside us or outside is, which is what he refers to as sensory experience, this feeling should be heeded, though morality is objective and universal more than not.

A11: “Common Critiques of Moral Rationalism

#1. Overemphasis on Reason Ignores Human Emotion

Critics argue that moral rationalism places too much trust in reason while overlooking the role of emotions in ethical decision-making. Emotions like empathy, guilt, and compassion often guide moral behavior. Psychologists such as Jonathan Haidt suggest that moral judgments are largely driven by intuition rather than logical reasoning.”

 

My response: Sentimentalism does have a place in ethical decision-making. I think moral judgments or choices made are driven by sensed or felt intuition as well as by rational intuition and logical reasoning.

 

It is easy to forget that the agent has a unitary consciousness if he is sane, happy, and psychologically healthy, so he will integrate his sentimental choosing with his rational choosing, and they will influence and exert pressure and likely alteration or modification upon each other along the way.

A11: “For example, people often feel moral disgust before they can rationally explain why something is wrong. If reason alone dictated morality, ethical decision-making would be mechanical and detached. Moral rationalism struggles to account for deeply ingrained emotional responses that influence real-world moral choices.

#2. Fails to Account for Moral Diversity and Disagreement

Different cultures and societies have varying moral codes, yet moral rationalism assumes that universal ethical principles exist. Critics argue that reason alone cannot resolve deep moral disagreements. Anthropological studies show that concepts of right and wrong differ widely, challenging the idea of objective moral laws.”

 

My response: It is my sense of things that there are moral laws detectable, definable, universal, and objective which are primary and shared by all societies, in spite of local color and variations.

A11: “For instance, some cultures see individual autonomy as central to morality, while others emphasize collective responsibility. If morality were purely rational, universal agreement on ethical principles should follow. However, the existence of ongoing moral disputes suggests that reason alone may be insufficient to determine moral truth.”

 

My response: All peoples with competing moral codes does not negate moral reasoning because most peoples are irrational, emotional, enjoying their cultural confirmation bias and ethnocentric chauvinism.

Despite this, there are universal, shared values, at closer inspection, at work in all cultures and all moral codes, and this points to moral univeralism and moral objectivity; still moral relativism and moral subjectivity do inform the moderated moral agent.

A11: “#3. Neglects the Role of Culture and Context

Moral rationalism assumes that ethical principles are independent of social and historical context. Critics argue that morality is shaped by cultural norms, traditions, and historical experiences rather than pure reason. Sociologists like Emile Durkheim emphasize that moral beliefs develop through social structures, not abstract reasoning.

For example, the moral status of practices like capital punishment or animal rights depends on societal attitudes. What is considered morally acceptable in one era may be condemned in another. This suggests that moral rationalism underestimates the influence of cultural and historical factors in shaping ethical views.”

My response: Yes, the role of culture and context must be accounted for when devising a set of objective ethical principles for all peoples to live in accordance with.

A11: “#4. Assumes Morality Is Always Objective

Moral rationalists argue that ethical truths are objective and universal. Critics challenge this by pointing out that moral principles often depend on subjective perspectives and changing human values. Ethical subjectivists argue that morality is influenced by personal experiences rather than absolute laws.

For example, debates over euthanasia or abortion reveal how moral values differ based on individual worldviews. If moral rationalism were correct, reason alone should resolve such disputes. However, deep disagreements persist, indicating that morality may not be as objective and universal as rationalists claim.”

My response: If warring peoples with clashing ethical codes would seek for logical, honorable compromise in the spirit of moderate blending of conflicting codes where possible, in a reasonably consistent manner, then both peoples may come closer to capturing what is a compromise approaching the desired universal and objective moral code.

A11: “#5. Cannot Fully Explain Moral Motivation

Even if reason identifies moral duties, critics argue that it does not necessarily motivate people to act morally. David Hume famously claimed that “reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions,” suggesting that emotions, not reason, drive moral action. Rationalists struggle to explain why knowing the right thing to do does not always lead to moral behavior.

For example, someone may rationally understand that lying is wrong but still lie for personal gain. This suggests that morality involves more than logical reasoning. Emotional impulses, social influences, and personal incentives often play a stronger role in ethical choices than abstract principles.”

My response: People are group creatures guided by altruistic-collectivist morality, so this makes them more humble and sentimental, so that explains why emotional impulse, social influences and personal incentive motivate where as dry abstract principles do not. A generation of rational, intellectual individuating supercitizens would be better motivated to be motivated ethically by dry abstract ethical principles.

A11: “#6. Leads to Cold or Detached Ethical Judgments

Because moral rationalism prioritizes logic over feelings, critics argue that it can lead to rigid or emotionally detached moral judgments. Ethical decisions often require understanding human suffering, something that pure reason may fail to capture. Moral philosophers like Martha Nussbaum argue that emotions are essential for moral insight.

For example, applying Kant’s universal laws strictly might lead to conclusions that feel morally inadequate. Imagine refusing to lie to protect someone from harm simply because lying is universally wrong. This highlights the potential coldness of a purely rational moral framework that ignores compassion and situational factors.”

My response: Here it seems that feelings, compassion, and a personal reading of situational factors would be critical to be informed as how to act.

A11: “#7. Underestimates the Influence of Intuition

Many moral decisions happen instantly, without conscious reasoning. Critics argue that moral intuition, rather than logical analysis, often determines ethical choices. Studies in moral psychology, such as those by Joshua Greene, show that people rely on gut feelings rather than slow, rational deliberation.

For example, when faced with a moral dilemma, most people react instinctively before forming a rational justification. If reason were the primary guide, ethical decisions would be made through careful logical reflection. However, everyday moral behavior suggests that intuition and subconscious processes play a far greater role than moral rationalism acknowledges.”

My response: Sentimental intuition and subconscious processes are not be be ignored.

A11: “”#8. Struggles with Moral Dilemmas Requiring Compassion

Some ethical situations require compassion over strict reasoning. Moral rationalism struggles when rules conflict or when following pure logic results in morally troubling outcomes. Ethics often requires flexibility, whereas rationalist approaches demand strict consistency.

For example, rigid adherence to universal moral laws might prevent morally acceptable exceptions. A doctor lying to comfort a dying patient may be ethically justified, yet a strict rationalist might argue that lying is always wrong. These cases show that morality often depends on empathy and situational understanding, which pure reason alone cannot always provide.”

 

My response: Yes, compassion, common sense, sound judgment and moral sense must balance out pure reasoning about moral choices.

A11: “Conclusion

Moral rationalism argues that reason is the foundation of morality. It claims that ethical truths are objective, universal, and discoverable through logical analysis. Thinkers like Kant, Plato, and Spinoza built ethical systems based on rational principles rather than emotions or traditions.

However, critics argue that moral rationalism overlooks the role of emotions, culture, and intuition in ethical decision-making. While reason provides consistency and structure, moral motivation often comes from feelings and social influences.

Understanding both the strengths and weaknesses of moral rationalism helps in evaluating how reason shapes morality and where it may fall short in real-world ethics.

© 2025 This is Rationalism

 

 

 

 

                                                       M

 

 

 

 

                                       

Article 12 (A12 after this) “Chapter

10 Is It Rational to Be Moral?

Shaun Nichols

https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198869153.003.0010

Pages

211–226

·       Published:

February 2021

·        

Abstract

Why should all rational agents be moral? This is one ancient and challenging question about moral motivation. But there is another perhaps more tractable question about moral motivation. Why as a matter of fact are most of us motivated by moral considerations? What is it about the kind of creature I am that inclines me to be moral? Moral judgments (e.g. that it’s right to give to a certain charity) seem to be directly motivating. This chapter argues that even non-moral normative judgments often are directly motivating. A primary form of rule representation automatically carries with it motivation force.”

My response: It seems that the author of this article is arguing that nonmoral normative judgments can be motivating, and these normoral judgments might be feeling based and feeling generated.

 

 

                                                N

 

                                               

 

Article 13 (A 13 after this): “Psychology Fanatics Logo

Moral Reasoning

Article, Psychology / November 25, 2023 / By T. Franklin Murphy / 10 minutes of reading

·       Home

·       Psychology

·       Moral Reasoning

Moral Reasoning: Understanding the Foundation of Ethical Decision-Making

In the labyrinth of the human psyche, moral reasoning emerges as a beacon of light, guiding us through the fog of ethical dilemmas. It is the silent whisper of conscience that speaks when we stand at the crossroads of right and wrong. This intricate dance of judgment, woven into the very fabric of our being, is not merely a cognitive process but an emotional symphony that plays out in the theater of the mind. As we embark on this exploration of moral reasoning, we delve into the depths of our moral compass, seeking to understand the invisible forces that shape our decisions and forge our character in the crucible of life’s complex moral landscapes.”

 

My response: Murphy seems to promise that the agent as moral reasoner will follow his head and logic but his heart informs his decisions, and sometimes outright makes his decisions for him.

 

 

A13: “Key Definition:

Moral Reasoning is a cognitive process of integrating moral and ethical elements into a decision or behavior.

What is Moral Reasoning?

Moral reasoning refers to the cognitive process through which individuals determine the morality or ethicality of a particular action or situation. It involves evaluating various moral principles, values, and ethical theories to arrive at a moral judgment. Moral reasoning helps us weigh the consequences of our actions and evaluate whether they align with our personal values and societal norms.

Moral reasoning requires an interruption in the stimulus response continuum, allowing for cognitive process to retrieve additional moral and ethical factors into working memory before making a decision or proceeding with an impulsive action. Daniel J. Siegel wrote that “when we are reactive, we revert to primitive behaviors without flexibility or compassion. We act impulsively, lose the ability to balance our emotions, and fail to exert moral reasoning” (Siegel, 2009, Kindle location: 4,489).

Daniel J. Siegel wrote “moral awareness as I’m using it here denotes the ways in which we both think about and enact behaviors for the social good, and we have evidence that it requires an intact middle prefrontal region.” He continues, “moral reasoning seems to require the integrative capacity of this region of the brain both to sense the emotional meaning of present challenges and to override immediate impulses in order to create moral action in response to those challenges” ( Siegel, 2009, Kindle location: 671).

Moral Reasoning and Emotions, and Justification

Siegel “research on emotion, for example, demonstrates the intimate influence of emotion on all cognitive processes, from attention and perception to memory and moral reasoning” (Siegel, 2020, Kindle Location: 5,474). Often, we react to emotional reactions first and engage moral reasoning afterwards. Emotions may actually be the underlying motivator of ethical behavior. Basically, when we internalize certain ethics and values, they function without intentional reasoning. Accordingly, violating these values indices discomforting emotions and honoring them brings positive emotions. In behaviorism, this is referred to as conditioning.”

My response: I am skeptical that our emotions are the underlying motivator of our ethical behavior.

A13: “Research supports this theory. Leland F. Saunders wrote, “in many cases it appears that reason has no causal role in moral judgment, and that emotions alone are a necessary, and often sufficient cause of moral judgment” (Saunders, 2017). Consequently, it appear that moral reasoning is more than simple practical wisdom and ethics. Like much of human behavior, complexities intrude and create a slightly less clear picture than we would prefer. Anthony O’Hear wrote “the acquisition of practical wisdom requires an intertwined development of character and reason, alongside a growing…immersion in the complexities and intricacies of life” (O’Hear, 2020).”

My response: Reason has no causal role in moral judgment—I do not buy it.

A13: “Moral Justification

Moral reasoning seems like a beneficial practice that we should all employ. However, because morals are not universal, the morals we personally draw on may be flawed. Moreover, we may consciously acknowledge certain morals, yet only apply them when they build up our ego, ignoring them in other situations that require more moral courage. We engage in what is termed situational ethics. We only apply moral reasoning when it fits our situation without extensive sacrifice. While we allow emotions and circumstances to dictate our behavior, we typically don’t give others the same latitude.

According to Albert Bandura we internalize laws that regulate our behavior through self sanctions. However, when our behaviors violate these self sanctions, shunning the internalized ethical laws, we justify. We address the cognitive dissonance of conflicting morals and behaviors through a number of defensive strategies.

According to moral disengagement theory, moral justification refers to the process of framing harmful actions or behaviors in a way that makes them seem morally acceptable or justified. Paradoxically, we may use our morals as a means of excusing immoral behavior. We choose which moral to use and which one to ignore.

See Moral Justification for more on this topic

Support Free Journalism

The Dangers of Moral Reasoning

One of the problems with moral reasoning is we use it to judge others. We take our own particular morals or ethics and project in on all others. In some cases this may be appropriate in a limited fashion. For example, I believe we shouldn’t harm others except in extreme circumstances. I can moralize hurtful actions of others as inappropriate in society. However, we often use moral reasoning in a much broader sense, judging others against or own cultural upbringing, labelling them as ‘bad’ because they are different.

Steven Pinker warns that “most activities that moral people extol…are “biological errors” and are utterly unnatural in the rest of the living world.” Basically, we have certain moral values to guide and explain our personal behavior and then project those values onto others. Many times biases are ignorant to biological givens behind behavior. We judge with moralistic thoughts while ignoring biological correlates motivating the others behaviors.

Pinker adds that, “our network of fuzzy associations naturally reverts to a stereotype when we first encounter an individual. But our rule-based categorizer can block out those associations and make deductions based on the relevant facts about that individual. It can do so either for practical reasons, when information about a group-wide average is less diagnostic than information about the individual, or for social and moral reasons, out of respect for the imperative that one ought to ignore certain group-wide averages when judging an individual” (Pinker, 2003, Kindle location: 4,466).

The Components of Moral Reasoning

Moral Principles

Moral principles serve as the fundamental basis for moral reasoning. These principles often vary across cultures and individuals, but some common examples include honesty, fairness, justice, autonomy, and empathy. Moral reasoning involves considering these principles and applying them to specific situations to determine the ethical course of action.

Ethical Theories

Ethical theories provide frameworks or perspectives that help individuals analyze and evaluate ethical dilemmas. Some widely recognized ethical theories include utilitarianism, deontology, virtue ethics, and ethical relativism. These theories offer different perspectives on how to determine the morality of an action by considering factors such as the consequences of the action, the intentions behind it, or the character of the person involved.

Cognitive Processes

Moral reasoning involves cognitive processes such as logical thinking, moral judgment, ethical analysis, and reflection. These processes enable individuals to assess the various factors involved in a moral dilemma and consider different viewpoints. It requires us to engage our critical thinking skills and evaluate the ethical implications of our actions.

The Stages of Moral Reasoning

Lawrence Kohlberg, a renowned psychologist, proposed a theory of moral development that outlines different stages of moral reasoning. While individuals may not progress through each stage linearly, understanding these stages can shed light on how moral reasoning evolves and develops.

1. Pre-conventional Level:

At this stage, individuals’ moral reasoning is based on self-interest and avoiding punishment. Right and wrong are determined by what is beneficial or harmful to oneself. Individuals focus on the consequences of their actions for themselves rather than considering broader ethical principles.””

My response: I do not doubt there are progressive levels of moral development, but right away as an egoist-individualist, I take offense that Kohlberg assigns his lowest level of adult moral development to an individual pursuing his self-interest rather than considering broader ethical principles.

Kohlberg is an altruist-collectivist, or utilitarian of some kind. I would counterargue that the group-loving, group-living, nonindividuating moral agent, joiner, and conformist, morally reasons as a groupist, and this is the lowest level of normal adult moral development.

 

A13: “2. Conventional Level:

During this stage, individuals begin to consider societal norms and expectations. Moral reasoning is influenced by a desire to maintain social order and gain acceptance within a community. Right and wrong are determined by adhering to societal rules and fulfilling one’s social obligations.”

 

My response This Convention Level of moral development from Kohlberg seems to be how an ordinary human develops and is socialized as an altruist and moral adult in everyday society, though I think they could go farther if egoistic and individuating.

A13: “3. Post-conventional Level:

At the post-conventional level, individuals transcend societal norms and develop their own moral principles. Moral reasoning is based on universal ethical principles and a deep understanding of justice, equality, and individual rights. Individuals at this stage critically evaluate social conventions and may be willing to disobey unjust laws (Murphy, 2022).”

My response: The Kohlberg Post-conventional Level of moral development seems like the level most convivial too and correspondent with the ethical disposition and pondering of an adult maverizer.

Of course this would grow out of more altruistic Conventional Level of development, complementing and extending rather than vying and replacing simpler more collective moral choosing.

A13: “Most middle class Americans reach the level of conventional reasoning by age 36 (Damasio, 2005).

See Kohlberg’ Theory of Moral Development for more on this theory”

 

Enhancing Moral Reasoning

Some therapies, such as moral reconation therapy, focuses on developing stronger morals and enhanced moral reasoning skills. The idea is that through more effective use of moral reasoning a person can better direct their lives.

Moral reasoning is not fixed but can be nurtured and enhanced through continuous self-reflection, learning, and exposure to diverse perspectives. Here are a few strategies to strengthen your moral reasoning skills:

  • Cultivate empathy: Seek to understand and empathize with different people’s perspectives and experiences. This can broaden your understanding of ethical dilemmas and help you consider multiple viewpoints.
  • Reflect on personal values: Reflect on your core values and how they align with various moral principles. Consider how your values influence your decision-making and whether they need to be reassessed or expanded.
  • Study ethical theories: Familiarize yourself with different ethical theories to gain insight into alternative perspectives on moral reasoning. This can enhance your ability to analyze complex ethical dilemmas and make well-informed decisions.
  • Engage in ethical discussions: Engaging in thoughtful discussions and debates about ethical issues with others can help refine your moral reasoning skills. It allows you to consider diverse opinions and challenge your own beliefs.

Rushworth M Kidder suggests that we must emphasize intrinsic values over instrumental values. Basically, he explains that “they ground themselves in the really big, intrinsic values, including truth, respect, fairness, responsibility, and compassion. While they respect instrumental values (diligence, competitiveness, and so forth), they realize that these are as important to the Mafia as to themselves” (Kidder, 2009, Kindle location: 4,211).

Associated Concepts

  • Moral Disengagement Theory: This theory developed by Albert Bandura explores cognitive mechanisms enabling individuals to rationalize and justify unethical actions. It delves into mental processes used to disengage from moral standards.
  • Moral Justification: This is is a personal strategy we employ to excuse personal behaviors that conflict with internal ethical laws of behaviors.
  • Slippery Slope Fallacy: This is also known as the Domino Fallacy. This fallacy fallacy occurs when a person argues that a particular course of action or event will lead to a series of increasingly undesirable consequences, without sufficient evidence to support such a claim. This fallacy suggests that taking a small step in a certain direction will inevitably lead to a drastic or extreme outcome, often based on fear or speculation rather than logical reasoning.
  • Emotional Reasoning: The fallacy can be a form of emotional reasoning, where conclusions are drawn based on emotions rather than evidence. This is a common cognitive distortion in various psychological disorders.
  • Confirmation Bias: When people believe in the slippery slope argument, they may only seek out information that confirms their belief that the negative consequences will indeed follow, which is known as confirmation bias.
  • Primary Human Dilemma: This dilemma involves balancing personal needs with the desire for social acceptance. This internal conflict highlights the interplay between individual aspirations and societal expectations, impacting decision-making across various life aspects.”

My response: We always want to live in the truth, double-check our rationalizations, and seek further insight. We do not want to do or condone evil, and we must not use the above-mentioned, manipulative strategies to justify whatever we desire to do, though the choice is immoral.

A13: “A Few Words by Psychology Fanatic

Bear in mind that the odyssey of moral reasoning is not a sprint but a marathon without a finish line, a perpetual quest that beckons us to tread the path of self-examination and maturation. It is through the sharpening of our moral faculties that we can dissect ethical quandaries with sagacity and uprightness, steering our actions towards the greater good. As architects of our moral universe, we hold the power to sculpt a society that mirrors the highest ideals of justice and morality. So let us embrace this journey with a steadfast commitment to ethical evolution, for in the grand tapestry of humanity, each thread of moral reasoning we weave contributes to a more equitable and virtuous world.

Last Update: November 18, 2024”

 

 

 

                                                            O

 

 

Article 14: “How we make moral decisions

In some situations, asking “what if everyone did that?” is a common strategy for judging whether an action is right or wrong.

MIT News Office

Publication Date:

October 2, 2020

 

Caption:

Researchers at MIT and Harvard have shown that people use a type of reasoning known as universalization to help them make moral decisions in certain types of situations. This strategy is most applicable in social dilemmas called “threshold problems,” in which harm can occur if everyone, or a large number of people, perform a certain action.

Credits:

Image: iStock illustration edited by MIT News

Imagine that one day you’re riding the train and decide to hop the turnstile to avoid paying the fare. It probably won’t have a big impact on the financial well-being of your local transportation system. But now ask yourself, “What if everyone did that?” The outcome is much different — the system would likely go bankrupt and no one would be able to ride the train anymore.

Moral philosophers have long believed this type of reasoning, known as universalization, is the best way to make moral decisions. But do ordinary people spontaneously use this kind of moral judgment in their everyday lives?

In a study of several hundred people, MIT and Harvard University researchers have confirmed that people do use this strategy in particular situations called “threshold problems.” These are social dilemmas in which harm can occur if everyone, or a large number of people, performs a certain action. The authors devised a mathematical model that quantitatively predicts the judgments they are likely to make. They also showed, for the first time, that children as young as 4 years old can use this type of reasoning to judge right and wrong.

“This mechanism seems to be a way that we spontaneously can figure out what are the kinds of actions that I can do that are sustainable in my community,” says Sydney Levine, a postdoc at MIT and Harvard and the lead author of the study.

Other authors of the study are Max Kleiman-Weiner, a postdoc at MIT and Harvard; Laura Schulz, an MIT professor of cognitive science; Joshua Tenenbaum, a professor of computational cognitive science at MIT and a member of MIT’s Center for Brains, Minds, and Machines and Computer Science and Artificial Intelligence Laboratory (CSAIL); and Fiery Cushman, an assistant professor of psychology at Harvard. The paper is appearing this week in the Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences.

Judging morality

The concept of universalization has been included in philosophical theories since at least the 1700s. Universalization is one of several strategies that philosophers believe people use to make moral judgments, along with outcome-based reasoning and rule-based reasoning. However, there have been few psychological studies of universalization, and many questions remain regarding how often this strategy is used, and under what circumstances.

To explore those questions, the MIT/Harvard team asked participants in their study to evaluate the morality of actions taken in situations where harm could occur if too many people perform the action. In one hypothetical scenario, John, a fisherman, is trying to decide whether to start using a new, more efficient fishing hook that will allow him to catch more fish. However, if every fisherman in his village decided to use the new hook, there would soon be no fish left in the lake.

The researchers found that many subjects did use universalization to evaluate John’s actions, and that their judgments depended on a variety of factors, including the number of people who were interested in using the new hook and the number of people using it that would trigger a harmful outcome.

To tease out the impact of those factors, the researchers created several versions of the scenario. In one, no one else in the village was interested in using the new hook, and in that scenario, most participants deemed it acceptable for John to use it. However, if others in the village were interested but chose not to use it, then John’s decision to use it was judged to be morally wrong.

The researchers also found that they could use their data to create a mathematical model that explains how people take different factors into account, such as the number of people who want to do the action and the number of people doing it that would cause harm. The model accurately predicts how people’s judgments change when these factors change.

In their last set of studies, the researchers created scenarios that they used to test judgments made by children between the ages of 4 and 11. One story featured a child who wanted to take a rock from a path in a park for his rock collection. Children were asked to judge if that was OK, under two different circumstances: In one, only one child wanted a rock, and in the other, many other children also wanted to take rocks for their collections.

The researchers found that most of the children deemed it wrong to take a rock if everyone wanted to, but permissible if there was only one child who wanted to do it. However, the children were not able to specifically explain why they had made those judgments.

“What's interesting about this is we discovered that if you set up this carefully controlled contrast, the kids seem to be using this computation, even though they can't articulate it,” Levine says. “They can't introspect on their cognition and know what they're doing and why, but they seem to be deploying the mechanism anyway.”

In future studies, the researchers hope to explore how and when the ability to use this type of reasoning develops in children.

Collective action

In the real world, there are many instances where universalization could be a good strategy for making decisions, but it’s not necessary because rules are already in place governing those situations.

“There are a lot of collective action problems in our world that can be solved with universalization, but they're already solved with governmental regulation,” Levine says. “We don't rely on people to have to do that kind of reasoning, we just make it illegal to ride the bus without paying.”

However, universalization can still be useful in situations that arise suddenly, before any government regulations or guidelines have been put in place. For example, at the beginning of the Covid-19 pandemic, before many local governments began requiring masks in public places, people contemplating wearing masks might have asked themselves what would happen if everyone decided not to wear one.

The researchers now hope to explore the reasons why people sometimes don’t seem to use universalization in cases where it could be applicable, such as combating climate change. One possible explanation is that people don’t have enough information about the potential harm that can result from certain actions, Levine says.

The research was funded by the John Templeton Foundation, the Templeton World Charity Foundation, and the Center for Brains, Minds, and Machines.

Paper

Paper: "The logic of universalization guides moral judgment"

 

My response: I detect no necessary conflict between universalization (Would everyone be good if they did what I am thinking of doing?) and individualism; both loners and egoistic individuators or nonindividuators, joiners and altruistic, could reason if the considered action is worthy or not, if all were free to so choose and so act.

 

                                                            P

 

 

Article 15: “People also ask

What is moral reasoning in ethics?

  • Inherent in the study of ethics is a crucial understanding of the concept of objectivity. Moral reasoning is the series of factors, arguments, and thinking patterns that humans use or engage in to determine what the basic values or constructs of proper moral judgments should be.”

My response: We need moral reasoning to know how to act and how to proceed.

 

Q

 

Article 16 (A16 after this):”

 

Logo for University System of New Hampshire Pressbooks

Primary Navigation

Analyzing the basics of ethical thinking for leaders and organizations in society

This chapter will introduce the basic constructs of moral thinking. We will begin by defining the terms morality and ethics.  After creating a working knowledge of the terminology, we will look at the roots of moral decision-making in our society by tracing the factors contributing to the Western societal framework. We will examine the many characteristics, including inherent tensions, that determine individual morality and societal ethics while focusing on the inherent legacy and discussion in that interaction. At the end of this section, different conceptions of the more profound components of moral theory and its interaction in society will be introduced, with constructive and practical outcomes that will help us to determine how best to approach ethical outcomes. This will include suggestions on becoming more aware of moral decision-making and how to avoid potential problems organizations or leaders might face as they consider problems that we must address personally, professionally, and in a societal and/or global sense.

Key Definitions

What is Morality?

The constructs of human conduct and/or values.

What is Ethics?

The study of the constructs that determine what is good and evil in direct connection with moral principles and values

What is Moral Reasoning?

The factors, arguments, and thinking patterns that determine the constructs of human conduct and/or values

Let’s begin with basic definitions of the study of moral philosophy and “good” decision-making.  Morality is the term used to describe the constructs of human conduct and/or values.  At its base, morality is formulated on an understanding of preferred behavior, in both an individual and societal sense, depending on the context.  It is often in the interaction of personal and societal factors that thinkers have contemplated the depth and uniqueness of this study. Though many theorists differ in their interpretation of how morality is derived personally and collectively, experts generally agree that morality is a combination of reason and “sense” that we use or fall back on to determine right from wrong or our expectations of ourselves and others.”

My response: If morality is a combination of reason and sense—and it is—then sensing the nature of a choice, a person’s character, or an action, all might be intuited rationally or sentimentally, and that seems right to me.

 A16: “Using the writings of Plato in commentary on Socrates, the definition focuses on morality as the determination of “how we ought to live.”  This understanding of morality coincides with our beliefs about the future and how we conceive of how the world, the people, and the factors that determine that reality should come to be and the result we desire.

Ethics is the formal study of the personal and collective definitions of morality. Ethics focuses on how we, individually or collectively, conceive or determine morality. It represents the constant reevaluation and thinking behind the decisions that have led us to these conclusions.

“Ethics” is derived from the Greek term “ethos.” This term was most closely connected to the Greek concept of “proper character or manners.” The definition of ethics, whether used as a discipline or conceptually, is focused on pursuing objective truth to determine better outcomes daily for everyone, regardless of the factors or the results. Inherent in the study of ethics is a crucial understanding of the concept of objectivity.”

My response: I would like to introduce to the reader that a moral egoist would be someone of proper character and excellent manners. If he is not courteous to God, others, and himself, he does not love the self, so he is not good, not his character, nor his will.

A16: “Moral reasoning is the series of factors, arguments, and thinking patterns that humans use or engage in to determine what the basic values or constructs of proper moral judgments should be. Moral reasoning focuses on why and/or how we achieve the result of a proper way of living life.  Though this is complicated, we all engage in this reasoning daily and throughout our lives, whether we consciously know it or not.

Two questions are at the core of this evaluation:

  1. What is the best course of thought and action required to improve our awareness of this reasoning?
  2. How do we determine the best outcome personally and as we interact and build community with others?

These terms are crucial to consider as we work towards the conceptual goal of truth. It includes how to read individuals more carefully and diligently and how we know ourselves.  By paying more close attention to these constructs and studying them in greater depth, a good thinker can understand the factors that determine better decisions and, of course, avoid the prospect of decisions that could be very costly.

Crucial Moral Concepts

What is Virtue?

The concept of moral excellence or proper moral conduct

What are Values?

Characteristics of human thought and action that are intrinsically preferred or held in high esteem

Building on these definitions, we turn our attention to two concepts that are crucial to ethical study.  Virtue is defined as the concept of moral excellence or proper moral conduct.  This term is also applied to a field of ethical study called “virtue ethics.”  “Virtue” philosophical thinkers believe there is a core of attributes central to the human condition that we can determine or “call upon” as preferred attributes of human behavior.  These theories are most widely studied in the framework of Ancient Greek philosophers, including Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, who is perhaps the most famous.  We will look at their views in the future.  Many of these thinkers believe that ethical thinking becomes self-evident as individuals learn more about themselves and their world.

From that wisdom development, concepts of preferred behavior emerge. A good example is courage. Using reason, it becomes clear that being courageous is always more desirable than being uncourageous. Though people can be “courageous” or “uncourageous,” conceptually, courageous behavior is often believed to be more virtuous or an element of proper moral conduct.  In our study, we pay particular attention or think about what determines a better or wiser thinker and what it requires of us.  In Damon Horowitz’s 3-minute talk on teaching philosophy in prison, listen to his assessment of the importance and power of philosophical training and thought as it relates to determining the practical nature of the definition of virtue.  What essential components of this conversation should we consider as we contemplate what it means to pursue ethical thinking?  Those components of wisdom or attributes observed in human experience often coincide with the concepts that thinkers of the ages have determined are central to the “virtue” ethical excellence elements.

The other term essential to the discussion of morality and decision-making is the definition of values.  The baseline definition of the term “values” pertains to human thought and action characteristics that are intrinsically preferred or held in high esteem.  For our purposes, consider the term “values” or “value” as the individual characteristics, like courage, that make up the concept of virtuous or proper moral conduct.  These two terms remind us that ideals or concepts may be present in our daily decision-making.  The key is to identify them, ensure those ideals are central to objective truth and not just what we want, and consciously allow them to guide us in all aspects of our lives.”

 

 

                                                            R

Article 17 (A17 after this): “Basic Constructs of Ethical Study

Descriptive Ethics + Analytical Ethics = Normative Ethics

The determination of values and/or virtues can be seen in the struggle of leaders and organizations over time.  In the Twentieth Century and the Twenty-First Century, unethical decisions have dominated the world, resulting in unethical outcomes.  In the wake of such damaging outcomes, people are more astutely focusing on ethics and ethical practice.  In doing so, they consider greater thoughtful procedures as they scope through risk management, organizational function and productivity, market positioning, and civic responsibility. What has emerged in greater clarity is the understanding that profits and ethical decision-making, at all levels, can be integrated partners if consistent and committed to long-term success is kept at the forefront of individual consciousness.

At the beginning of the study of ethical options, we need to define a framework to understand how to study ethics.  In doing this, it becomes clear that ethics is complicated and not merely a formulation of what is only “wrong” or “right” but a concentrated and in-depth study of the various segments of human thought and behavior.  I term this complexity the equation of ethical study.  There are three components:

  1. Descriptive ethics is the branch of ethical study that considers ethical analysis in the context of a neutral representation of the perceptions or facts of any ethical situation.  It involves a lengthy and careful attempt to identify the ethical issues and values inherent in the evaluation process.
  2. Analytical ethics centers on the argument and logic in the ethical opinions and assessments used to determine the ethical issues, values, or outcomes.  This approach builds on descriptive ethics by considering the construct of ethical determination in greater depth.  Analytical ethics considers the ethical outcome based upon other decisions, especially those decisions that are disconnected from others and the impact such decisions or outcomes might have in that consideration.
  3. Normative ethics approaches the study of ethics with the belief, according to Kitson and Campbell in Case Studies in Business Ethics (2001), of seeking “to develop and defend judgments of right and wrong, good and bad, and virtue and vice, to arrive at an understanding of truth.”  This final evaluation tool process focuses on determining the best possible outcome after solid and productive consideration of descriptive and analytical components.  Normative is usually the stage of the ethical evaluation process that most people are familiar with, as it often leads to a decision or determination of what is “right” or “wrong” for an individual, group, organization, or society.

As May describes in Case Studies in Organizational Communication, these three layers make up the many different conceptualizations inherent in ethical analysis.  All are equally important, but we must consider the ethical layers when considering descriptive and analytical ethical standing to make the best possible decision.”

A17: “Prominent Ethical Tensions

Foundational vs. Situational Tensions

Individual vs. Community Tensions

Beyond these layers of ethical study, good critical thinkers must be aware of inevitable tensions between individuals crucial to ethical study evaluation.  Such tensions exist in our world and are at the root of ethical dilemmas.

The first tension focuses on the interaction between foundational and situational arguments.

  • Foundational ethical arguments are built upon the idea that proper ethical formulation is based upon “universal” constructs of ethical thinking or objective conceptualization. From this standpoint, ethical evaluation is determined by an objective assessment that the individual or organization using this approach deems accurate, regardless of context or situation.”

My response: This sounds like moral realism.

 

A17: “

  • Situational ethical arguments are formulated on the belief that ethical thinking is a product of consistent change and subjective conceptualizations based upon unique circumstances or each instance in which an ethical evaluation must occur. This presents tension as each perspective can often be at the root of ethical differences and misunderstandings.”

My response This sounds like moral anti-realism.

A17: “The other tension highlights the moral stances of ideologies linked to individualism and collectivism.

  • Individualistic ideology argues that proper ethical evaluation and determination are inherently formulated on the individual, entity, and responsibility.
  • The collective ethical perspective argues the opposite.”

My response: Collective morality is of secondary rank for the individual and society than is individual morality, but both are needed, and, counterintuitively, what is moral desirable is attainable by individual moralizing where the person is more rational, universalizing a potential behavior as the agent imagines objectively how such an action would causally impact the world, and what would be its consequences. He can be emotional, situational, subjective, and relativistic, but others have gone through this moral dilemma before, not just him—he is not that unique.

A17: “Ethical decision-making is best constructed through understanding the soundest course of thought and evaluation through group affiliation and agreement. Thinkers must consider the interplay of the rights and responsibilities of individuals with the rights and responsibilities of communities found in any society or organization (of people).”

 

My response: I disagree.

 

A17: “  A better understanding of the framework of ethical interaction allows us to contemplate productive outcomes more deeply for some of our most difficult moral problems. Awareness of these tensions is a start to becoming more productive in arriving at more ethical outcomes and defraying possible misunderstandings around the thoughts and behavior of those involved.

Moral Reasoning and Determination are not only…  A matter of opinion or personal taste.

This essential question is central to the discussion of moral decision-making:  isn’t morality simply a matter of opinion or personal taste?  This question represents a standard assumption on the part of many.  Other people view morality, ethical thinking, moral reasoning, virtue, and value or values, as simply relativistic or subjective. “Relativistic” refers to the belief that our understanding of truth (or what we believe in) is based on our evaluation or perspective. It can be argued that truth comes from a subjective conception, and this viewpoint carries great merit as we understand perception, thinking, and uniqueness. It is also true that moral reasoning or morality must probe more deeply than simply a belief or opinion we possess.  Good thinking requires that we investigate, process and evaluate as many components of possible ethical dilemmas and not only the use of our background, quick assessments, or sole emotional reactions to determine better practices or outcomes.

Relativistic statements of individuals must go further than a simple assertion that they might have on a subject; instead, as the philosopher Dr. James Rachels explains in The Elements of Moral Philosophy, we must employ moral reasoning and virtuous decision-making solidly and constructively, building on the reasoning that is supported by the soundness of thought and consistency of action.  This Starburst candy advertisement demonstrates how important it is to determine when an opinion or personal taste should lead us to evaluate the Truth and how we might begin to use reason to help us transcend evaluations that might be problematic or untrue.”

 

 

 

 

                                                            S

 

Article 18 (A 18 after this): “

Basic Ethical Constructs of the Western World

Though there are many codes of moral conduct and varying traditions of ethical perspective we could study, I have limited the scope of this course to a series of very strong contributors to our Western world to illustrate how ethical theory and conception have come to define our reality.  These factors have become prominent in some ethical determinations in the Western World and the world at large.  As we consider the climate of increasing globalized networks built upon some of these notions, it is increasingly essential to constructively understand and evaluate the roots of such basic conceptions of morality.

The long conversational history becomes apparent in tracing the background of morality and ethical conduct.  We can find those essential modern conceptions linked to the world of the ancient world of the Greeks and Romans.  Our presumptions of good business, proper conduct, and even the truth of reality have been shaped by the writings and beliefs of individuals predating the fourth century BC.  Central to the Greco-Roman world was the philosophical viewpoint that the meaning of life was somehow connected to this idea of creating a “better life” or moving towards a greater sense of “progress.”

This idea is still present in almost every aspect of our world and can be fundamentally seen in Western culture.  This concept of “betterment” or “good” living has impacted our decision-making, creating a society that focuses on growth and the belief that there are better ways to approach various subjects and our lives.

One key component of this Greek belief of “betterment” can be traced to their solid ethical notion of the citizenry and civic responsibility.  Citizens have rights given to them by circumstance or situation, but with rights come responsibilities required of those with privilege.  The Romans took this concept further, believing that the true notion of justice was steeped in ethical importance.  They attempted to set up courts and impartial authority figures connected with the Roman authorities who were tasked with helping those in conflict resolve their issues through productive and just outcomes.  The idea was that society only operates ethically when people are treated fairly and problems are solved to diminish conflict.”

My response This last paragraph is acceptable but egoistic individuals more than altruistic joiners are the most moral, the most likely to take responsibility for themselves, others, and society.

A18: “The second component is the influence of Christian values and virtues on the development of accepted social norms of thought and behavior in the Western world.  Regardless of one’s religious affiliation, the Western world has been developed using the beliefs Christian principles passed down since the Middle Ages by the Roman Catholic Church.

During this time, many social norms espoused by the Christian establishment became the backbone of European society. They laid the foundation for individual and organizational behavior through law or cultural expectations.  Many of those expectations often associated with Hebraic belief expectations, such as the Ten Commandments, were combined with the teachings of Jesus Christ found in the New Testament.  Those expectations became encapsulated in Christian creeds and lists of behavioral expectations, such as The Seven Deadly Sins, decided by Christian leaders through council decisions.  These decisions were often instituted as laws that kingdoms adopted.  Many concepts of societal values, such as true justice and characteristics of personal values, were taught, reinforced, and passed down from generation to generation, both societally and individually.  In addition, these values or moral expectations were also taught and reinforced in direct conjunction with the Church’s practices.

Beyond the first earlier Western influences we have discussed, there have also been economic ideologies that have come to shape moral thinking and evaluation.  Milton Friedman, one of the most prominent economists of the twentieth century, argued, in a famous 1970 essay termed Friedman’s Thesis, as well as his early text Capitalism and Freedom, “the social responsibility of business is to increase its profits” arguing that the role of a business should be to maximize profits and not to be concerned with elements of moral responsibility or participate in determining moral “rights” and “wrongs’ within society.  According to his evaluation, institutions, especially for-profit organizations, should only concern themselves with economic decisions that would increase the profitability of shareholders. In this way, morality and market interaction would dictate proper moral decision-making.”

My response: The business of business is business and profits rule supreme, but ethical conduct must be factored in too.

A18: “Organizations’ freedom to pursue their best interest, namely profit, should determine organizational attitude and behavior as long as they obey the law.  This belief functioned under the assumption that moral assessments should be reserved for the citizens who would make those decisions by purchasing the products or services presented and through the regulations created by legislators who represented those citizens.  This approach profoundly influenced how Western society determined the best moral course of action, arguing that the market would be the best assessor of moral attitude and behavior.

Another layer of this debate centers itself on the tension between philanthropy and charity.  Philanthropy, the offering of financial or resource help to an individual, organization, or society in need with some benefit for the giving organization or individual, has often been interpreted by many as a productive way to invest in a beneficial, moral manner to address critical ethical problems.  It has been argued as the best option for addressing moral and social needs.  In doing so, though, the belief is that what is beneficial for those who need the help should be linked to the benefit of the participating organization.  Charity, in contrast, is centered on the idea that benefits of any kind should be offered without the mutual requirement of exchange.  The debate over what is proper and productive “help” and the morality of how to best offer it as we consider economic results have been at the crux of moral evaluation in the Western world and linked to the debate around Friedman’s Thesis.  Some of that debate has been influenced by moral presumptions connected with the value of work and individual responsibility.  This also includes the assumption that profitability is most important and should influence how we evaluate the most moral course of action.

The moral complexity of individual and society in Western society…Pluralism, dualism, and monism

As alluded to in the last section, the complexity of the interaction of individual and societal beliefs is critical in understanding the context of Western ethical thinking.  Western society has consistently attempted, through the institution of such documents as the Magna Carta, the English Bill of Rights 1688, and The Constitution of the United States, to define the relationship more clearly between what is individually acceptable behavior and what is collectively accepted as permissible

Rousseau, the famous French-Swiss philosopher of the eighteenth century, referred to this as the concept of a social contract.  At the heart of this interaction is a societal moral value called justice.  Perhaps one of the most controversial legal thinkers of the twentieth century, John Rawls, a prominent professor of law and philosophy at Harvard, asserts that we must know the role of “institutions” or groups of people in moral decision-making.  At the root of the interaction of personal, institutional (which is best defined as any group of individuals), and society at large is the philosophical conception of whether Truth, defined objectively, can be found in a dualistic thinking framework or a monistic thinking conceptualization.

Dualism is the belief that two concepts, ideals, or factors determine truth by their interplay or lack therein, while monism refers to the belief that truth reflects one concept, ideal, or factor.  For a thinker, it is imperative to determine whether problem-solving considers a more dualistic, or perhaps even pluralistic, or multiple-factor approach or a more monistic framework.  As we struggle with proper judgments, one will inevitably conclude that proper conduct and decision-making, as well as good critical thinking, must incorporate a solid and reliable set of rules of conduct or expectations that is inclusive of as many approaches or perspectives as possible while considering the need to determine ethical goals or ideals to progress towards.”

My response: As a moral moderate, it would seem to be that dualistic or pluralistic rival theories of moral ideals should be blended together, under one monistic, primary moral ideal.

A18: “Dilemmas at the Heart of Ethical Thinking…

  1. Justice vs. mercy
  2. Truth vs. Loyalty
  3. Individual vs. community
  4. Short-term goals vs. long-term goals

To further our understanding of ethical thinking, it is useful to dissect moral problems within the context of “value pairings.”  To highlight some of the more critical Western societal values, Rushworth Kidder breaks ethical issues into four major categories that should help us assess moral decision-making.  In How Good People Make Tough Choices:  Resolving the Dilemmas of Ethical Living (1995), he argues that all complex ethical dilemmas have, at their core, many of the following series of troubling pairings that make it challenging to determine the best moral outcome.

Justice versus mercy forces us to consider how we should uphold proper expectations for attitudes and behaviors, emphasizing that everyone should receive what they deserve within society.  This includes the belief that taking responsibility for oneself is important while balancing the belief that it is valuable to consider when to offer leniency to those who might not deserve it or someone who hasn’t taken responsibility.

Truth (objective) versus loyalty presents the dilemma of determining when we or society should adhere to the truth regardless of loyalty and when loyalty to ourselves, others, or institutions might be the most moral course of action.

The construct of individual versus community tension compels us to consider the varied interests of the individual versus the needs and/or desires of a greater community.  This moral dilemma can be present in many different facets of society.

Finally, Kidder iterates that the final dilemma we should consider is the clash between short-term and long-term goal-setting.  There are often compelling cases for when we should choose short-term over long-term goals or vice versa, but knowing when to make the right decision in the right situation is often difficult to determine.  Considering these four dilemmas can not be understated when we evaluate the importance of better critical thinking with the result of more ethical outcomes.  Listen to Patrick Awuah’s discussion (17 minutes) as he uses his experience to emphasize the importance of being a “thinking, moral” leader and how one should look for opportunities to encourage those traits in others.  Making ethical decisions is not easy, but it is necessary.”

My response: All four of these pairings are useful.

A18: “The Origin of Ethical Determination

Differing perspectives on moral determination have been considered in Western society for centuries.  As a result, many different viewpoints have emerged over time.  It is essential to contemplate the thoughts of some of the greatest thinkers to analyze what is truly at the core of proper moral reasoning and understand what many people today might conclude.

David Hume, a Scottish philosopher of the Eighteenth Century, espoused the viewpoint that people determine what is “right” or “wrong” through experiences filtered by their senses.  Hume’s famous statement that humans are nothing more than “a bundle of perceptions” claims that the core of who we are as individuals is directly tied to our perceptions or how we interpret the world.  Though perception, as a process, may be considered universal in the sense that we, as humans, all participate in it or employ the phenomena, he is quick to point out that each one of us is diverse in those experiences.

Karl Marx, the famous Mid-Nineteenth Century philosopher, is known primarily for his work The Communist Manifesto. Marx wrote that the root of ethical thinking is humans’ economic constraints. The struggle over material goods between those who have and those who have not and how that relationship is worked in society outlines and determines ethical thinking or morality.

The last and most controversial is the work of psychologist and psychoanalyst Sigmund Freud.  Freud believed that ethical thinking is directly tied to our subconscious and found that we find the real motivations for ethical decision-making in the interaction of the id, ego, and superego.  Therefore, morality is based upon our “hidden desires” or “what we really want” when played out against other influences such as societal expectations and/or the interests of others; this reflects the central feature of who we are as individuals but also the weighs that interest against the interest of others.

By contemplating the potential motivating factors that determine ethical thinking in people, we become much more careful in thinking through matters pertaining to decision-making.  In Western society, many thinkers have come to radically different perspectives on what determines ethical thought and action.

Questions at the Root of the Ethical Decision-Making Process

At the root of ethical decision-making are four initial questions that must be contemplated to find answers.

  1. What does it mean to be good?
  2. What makes a life a good life?
  3. What characteristics make up a good human?
  4. What duties do we have to each other and ourselves?

Critical thinkers may use the following suggestions when confronted with questions.

First, there are no easy answers; attaining satisfactory answers is ongoing.  These questions must be revisited to gain insight and enhance growth over time.

Second, strong and solid reasons require significant thought and the ability to continually question notions that might even be held dear.  Process and result must both be considered. Last, these questions require us to keep ourselves in check by considering the interest of others.”

My response: These four questions are critically important, and each individual must answer them for herself, and live in accordance with her answers to them.

A18: “Tough Outcomes May Emerge

Several potential outcomes emerge when important ethical questions are asked.  These questions can cause people to come to certain conclusions that may be unnerving. Additionally, the answers that people often struggle with produce actions and outcomes that present obstacles to moving along with better ethical thinking and problem-solving.

The first problem is the issue of blame.  At the root of blame is the shared realization that change is needed.  Change is often scary and threatening.  As individuals think about ethical issues, they are often confronted by their conscience or reason, prompting them to feel troubled by their thoughts or behaviors.  When integrated with the need to enact some form of change, discomfort can cause people to feel unmotivated or agitated.  It is probably safe to say that most humans do not like change, and this factor alone can cause uncomfortable situations or outcomes, but when we add the topic of moral assessment, there is added pressure and stress.  This video of a dog illustrates the humorous interaction between the dog “Denver” and his master.  This is a microcosm (in a more humorous manner) of what people might experience.

The second potential problem centers on the issue of obligation or duty.  Ethical issues naturally imply that the change required might dictate a strong sense of obligation that may cause people not to think and act unfairly. Think of a person who has a renewed view of an issue or problem and throws themselves completely into that new approach without realizing that that renewed perspective may not solve ethical issues.  The complexities of obligation can create a crisis as people, in their new understanding, might be torn between loyalties to multiple viewpoints or viewpoints—thus causing even more potential dismay.

The third factor to consider is the issue of the emotional investment of those involved.  Ethical issues often carry with them inherent strong viewpoints and feelings that can surface and may cause individuals to avoid an accurate understanding of the outcomes present.  This emotional investment may lead to false admiration for those involved in the decision or leaders who enact what is perceived to be the better moral decision or process.  This can lead to an inaccurate result or view of the situation.

Last might be the ethical dilemma of not knowing the result that an ethical decision might produce.  How does one truly know that they are correct, or what we have come to think is the proper outcome will indeed yield that result?  The prospect of this can be frightening for many people.  The more we know how people react in circumstances linked to ethical tensions and outcomes, the better we identify these tendencies in ourselves and others and work to allay those fears.  This is perhaps one of the most important factors to consider and why an ethics-based education is essential.

My response: It is well for the agent to realize that tough outcomes might arise should he undertake to change his choices, behavior, and character, but he must do what is right.

A18: “References

Awuah, P. (2007, June). How to educate leaders? Liberal arts. Retrieved from https://www.ted.com/talks/patrick_awuah_on_educating_leaders

Denver Official Guilty Dog Video. (2011, March 08). Retrieved from https://www.youtube.com/watch? v=B8ISzf2pryI

Horowitz, D. (2011, March). Philosophy in prison. Retrieved from https://www.ted.com/talks/damon_horowitz_philosophy_in_prison

Kitson, A., & Campbell, R. (2001). Case studies in business ethics. In A. Malachowski (Ed.), Business ethics: Critical perspectives on business and management (Vol. IV, pp. 7–12). London: Routledge.

May, S. (2012). Case studies in organizational communication: Ethical perspectives and practices. Thousand Oaks: SAGE Publications.

Rachels, S., & Rachels, J. (2019). The elements of moral philosophy. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill Education.

Ronda, N. (2011, June 19). Starburst- Commercial [funny]. Retrieved from https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=jodb9lkwnd8

 

 

 

                                                            T

Article 19 (A19 after this): “Do we really need to reason morally?”

My response: Yest, we really do need to reason morally.

A19: “What are some examples of moral reasoning?

  • These principles often vary across cultures and individuals, but some common examples include honesty, fairness, justice, autonomy, and empathy. Moral reasoning involves considering these principles and applying them to specific situations to determine the ethical course of action.

 

 

 

 

What is moral reasoning influenced by?

  • Moral reasoning is influenced by a desire to maintain social order and gain acceptance within a community. Right and wrong are determined by adhering to societal rules and fulfilling one’s social obligations. 3. Post-conventional Level:

 

 

 

How do you think about people morally reasoning with each other?

  • There are two salient and distinct ways of thinking about people morally reasoning with one another: as members of an organized or corporate body that is capable of reaching practical decisions of its own; and as autonomous individuals working outside any such structure to figure out with each other what they ought, morally, to do.”

 

 

   U

Article 20 (A20 after this): “

psychology

 

 

Moral Reasoning:

Moral reasoning refers to the process of making decisions based on moral principles and values. It involves evaluating different moral perspectives and considering the ethical implications of various choices or actions. Moral reasoning helps individuals determine what is right or wrong, just or unjust, and guides their behavior accordingly.”

My response: I admire and accept this paragraph as a definition of moral reasoning.

A20: “Components of Moral Reasoning:

1. Moral Principles:

Moral reasoning is built upon a foundation of moral principles, which are fundamental beliefs or rules that govern ethical behavior. These principles serve as guides for making moral judgments and may include concepts such as honesty, fairness, justice, compassion, and respect for others.

2. Ethical Dilemmas:

Ethical dilemmas are situations where individuals have to choose between conflicting moral values or courses of action. Moral reasoning enables individuals to analyze these dilemmas, consider the consequences of different choices, and arrive at a morally justifiable decision.

3. Ethical Reasoning Strategies:

Moral reasoning involves employing different strategies to evaluate ethical dilemmas. These strategies may include utilitarianism, deontological ethics, virtue ethics, and other ethical frameworks. Utilitarianism focuses on maximizing overall happiness or utility, while deontological ethics emphasizes adherence to moral duties and principles. Virtue ethics emphasizes developing virtuous character traits to guide ethical decision-making.

Stages of Moral Reasoning:

1. Pre-Conventional Reasoning:

In this stage, individuals make moral decisions based on self-interest and fear of punishment. Their reasoning is motivated by personal gain and the desire to avoid negative consequences. This stage is typically observed in young children.

2. Conventional Reasoning:

In the conventional stage, individuals base their moral judgments on social norms, rules, and expectations. They seek to maintain social order, gain approval from others, and uphold existing societal standards. This stage is often seen in adolescents and adults who prioritize societal expectations.

3. Post-Conventional Reasoning:

In the post-conventional stage, individuals develop their own ethical principles and reasoning independent of societal norms. They critically evaluate societal customs and laws, and prioritize universal ethical principles such as justice, equality, and human rights. This stage is reached by some adults who have undergone moral development beyond conventional reasoning.

Importance of Moral Reasoning:

Moral reasoning is crucial for individuals to navigate complex moral situations and make ethical decisions. It helps foster empathy, fairness, and respect for others, thereby contributing to the establishment of a just and harmonious society. Through moral reasoning, individuals can consider the consequences of their actions and align their behavior with ethical values, promoting moral growth and personal integrity.”

 

 

 

 

 

                                                            V

 

Since this entire blog entry is a take on my account of how human intellect, in each agent, can guide her to be a good person, that moral rationalism and moral sentimentalism both guide her ethical choosing, the heart is more evil than the head, but both can be abused, and both are needed to make wise, virtuous moral choices.

The agent’s conscience is integrated and interlocking if she is sane and functioning well, so the head and the heart work together to inspire her decision-making.

It seems to me that that the term will is near being a brute fact, that it may have an explanatory story, but it is hard to lay out with precision and certainty. Having said that, I will use the word will to serve as that moral faculty which is synonymous with the agent’s integrated consciousness in decision making.

If the individual is self-realizing, individual-living and guide by egoist ethics, then she will command and build a good will, under which she will utilize the hunches and realization from both her head and her heart to make generally, most of the time, wise moral choices, and this will help her stay on the straight and narrow path, applying her practical reasoning to choose the right choice, and to implement and carry out her choice selection, efficiently, with minimal negative consequences.

With her good will in place, operating and functioning on all burners, she will be a creature of love and loving, loving God, herself and others, and her veridical, high-self esteem and her solid but moderated self-pride, modestly displayed and communicated, will suffuse her with love, and love makes for possessing a good will, and a good will informs rationally and emotionally the agent how to make ethical decisions, and to better detect which choice is preferable.

Here is an entry from Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Moral Reasoning: let us see if this amateur thinker can make sense of a technical paper on moral reasoning. Here is the article:

Article 21(A21 after this): “Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Moral Reasoning

First published Mon Sep 15, 2003; substantive revision Mon Aug 27, 2018

While moral reasoning can be undertaken on another’s behalf, it is paradigmatically an agent’s first-personal (individual or collective) practical reasoning about what, morally, they ought to do. Philosophical examination of moral reasoning faces both distinctive puzzles – about how we recognize moral considerations and cope with conflicts among them and about how they move us to act – and distinctive opportunities for gleaning insight about what we ought to do from how we reason about what we ought to do.”

My response: It seems that we in first-person engage in moral reasoning about our individual needs and goals, versus our reasoning about collective needs and goals being met. We likely, if we are egoists, concentrate our moral reasoning about our individual interests, and if we are joiners, we as altruists focus on group plans and needs.  

A21: “Part I of this article characterizes moral reasoning more fully, situates it in relation both to first-order accounts of what morality requires of us and to philosophical accounts of the metaphysics of morality, and explains the interest of the topic. Part II then takes up a series of philosophical questions about moral reasoning, so understood and so situated.


1. The Philosophical Importance of Moral Reasoning

1.1 Defining “Moral Reasoning”

This article takes up moral reasoning as a species of practical reasoning – that is, as a type of reasoning directed towards deciding what to do and, when successful, issuing in an intention (see entry on practical reason).”

My response: If this article on moral reasoning is limited to practical reasoning, then the thrust of the article seems less metaethical, and more about applied ethics.”

 A21: “Of course, we also reason theoretically about what morality requires of us; but the nature of purely theoretical reasoning about ethics is adequately addressed in the various articles on ethics. It is also true that, on some understandings, moral reasoning directed towards deciding what to do involves forming judgments about what one ought, morally, to do. On these understandings, asking what one ought (morally) to do can be a practical question, a certain way of asking about what to do. (See section 1.5 on the question of whether this is a distinctive practical question.) In order to do justice to the full range of philosophical views about moral reasoning, we will need to have a capacious understanding of what counts as a moral question. For instance, since a prominent position about moral reasoning is that the relevant considerations are not codifiable, we would beg a central question if we here defined “morality” as involving codifiable principles or rules. For present purposes, we may understand issues about what is right or wrong, or virtuous or vicious, as raising moral questions.”

My response: I demur if philosophers generally deny morality as listing codifiable principles. That does not seem correct.

A21: “Even when moral questions explicitly arise in daily life, just as when we are faced with child-rearing, agricultural, and business questions, sometimes we act impulsively or instinctively rather than pausing to reason, not just about what to do, but about what we ought to do. Jean-Paul Sartre described a case of one of his students who came to him in occupied Paris during World War II, asking advice about whether to stay by his mother, who otherwise would have been left alone, or rather to go join the forces of the Free French, then massing in England (Sartre 1975). In the capacious sense just described, this is probably a moral question; and the young man paused long enough to ask Sartre’s advice. Does that mean that this young man was reasoning about his practical question? Not necessarily. Indeed, Sartre used the case to expound his skepticism about the possibility of addressing such a practical question by reasoning. But what is reasoning?”

My response: A sentimentalist would advance that it is acceptable to make moral decisions based upon our instincts, or feelings, and I cannot fault that, though choosing impulsively is a risky venture.

A21: “Reasoning, of the sort discussed here, is active or explicit thinking, in which the reasoner, responsibly guided by her assessments of her reasons (Kolodny 2005) and of any applicable requirements of rationality (Broome 2009, 2013), attempts to reach a well-supported answer to a well-defined question (Hieronymi 2013). For Sartre’s student, at least such a question had arisen. Indeed, the question was relatively definite, implying that the student had already engaged in some reflection about the various alternatives available to him – a process that has well been described as an important phase of practical reasoning, one that aptly precedes the effort to make up one’s mind (Harman 1986, 2).

Characterizing reasoning as responsibly conducted thinking of course does not suffice to analyze the notion. For one thing, it fails to address the fraught question of reasoning’s relation to inference (Harman 1986, Broome 2009). In addition, it does not settle whether formulating an intention about what to do suffices to conclude practical reasoning or whether such intentions cannot be adequately worked out except by starting to act. Perhaps one cannot adequately reason about how to repair a stone wall or how to make an omelet with the available ingredients without actually starting to repair or to cook (cf. Fernandez 2016). Still, it will do for present purposes. It suffices to make clear that the idea of reasoning involves norms of thinking. These norms of aptness or correctness in practical thinking surely do not require us to think along a single prescribed pathway, but rather permit only certain pathways and not others (Broome 2013, 219). Even so, we doubtless often fail to live up to them.”

My response: Practical reasoning as responsibly conducted reasoning is acceptable, and Stanford is correct that following the plan out inferentially helps, and getting started might clarify for the agent what to do in cases where she is unclear as how to proceed, or where to aim.

A21: “1.2 Empirical Challenges to Moral Reasoning

Our thinking, including our moral thinking, is often not explicit. We could say that we also reason tacitly, thinking in much the same way as during explicit reasoning, but without any explicit attempt to reach well-supported answers. In some situations, even moral ones, we might be ill-advised to attempt to answer our practical questions by explicit reasoning. In others, it might even be a mistake to reason tacitly – because, say, we face a pressing emergency. “Sometimes we should not deliberate about what to do, and just drive” (Arpaly and Schroeder 2014, 50). Yet even if we are not called upon to think through our options in all situations, and even if sometimes it would be positively better if we did not, still, if we are called upon to do so, then we should conduct our thinking responsibly: we should reason.”

My response: If our pathway to action is not explicitly clear, reasoned-out or defined for us, or if an emergency arises, often we just have to choose and then act, hoping our moral theory, our instincts, our guiding assumptions, and luck allow us to have chosen wisely. Often, we just have to move, for there is no time left.

A21: “Recent work in empirical ethics has indicated that even when we are called upon to reason morally, we often do so badly. When asked to give reasons for our moral intuitions, we are often “dumbfounded,” finding nothing to say in their defense (Haidt 2001). Our thinking about hypothetical moral scenarios has been shown to be highly sensitive to arbitrary variations, such as in the order of presentation. Even professional philosophers have been found to be prone to such lapses of clear thinking (e.g., Schwitzgebel & Cushman 2012). Some of our dumbfounding and confusion has been laid at the feet of our having both a fast, more emotional way of processing moral stimuli and a slow, more cognitive way (e.g., Greene 2014). An alternative explanation of moral dumbfounding looks to social norms of moral reasoning (Sneddon 2007). And a more optimistic reaction to our confusion sees our established patterns of “moral consistency reasoning” as being well-suited to cope with the clashing input generated by our fast and slow systems (Campbell & Kumar 2012) or as constituting “a flexible learning system that generates and updates a multidimensional evaluative landscape to guide decision and action” (Railton, 2014, 813).”

My response: If we are individuating egoist, that love ourselves, we then will more likely be in touch with our rational processes, and thus know better how to think and reason, and if are authentic, we will have a strong, clear conscience and so moral sense will generate directions for us that we will be confident to follow, though neither the cognitive and slow way of making moral decisions, or the emotional and fast way of making decisions are foolproof or infallible.

A21: “Eventually, such empirical work on our moral reasoning may yield revisions in our norms of moral reasoning. This has not yet happened. This article is principally concerned with philosophical issues posed by our current norms of moral reasoning. For example, given those norms and assuming that they are more or less followed, how do moral considerations enter into moral reasoning, get sorted out by it when they clash, and lead to action? And what do those norms indicate about what we ought to do do?”

My response: Since most people are joiners, illusion-lovers, and altruist-collectivists, the social norms they obey and reinforce will often lead to them making poor decisions, growing out of bad practical reasoning.

A21: “1.3 Situating Moral Reasoning

The topic of moral reasoning lies in between two other commonly addressed topics in moral philosophy. On the one side, there is the first-order question of what moral truths there are, if any. For instance, are there any true general principles of morality, and if so, what are they? At this level utilitarianism competes with Kantianism, for instance, and both compete with anti-theorists of various stripes, who recognize only particular truths about morality (Clarke & Simpson 1989).”

My response: Metaphysically, I am mostly a cognitivist, a moral objectivist, and a Modernist, from which it follows that moral theories are the grand narratives of ethics, mostly meaningful and helpful in normative and applied ethical situations.

Yes, the moderate in me allows for some moral noncognitivism, moral subjectivity, and postmodernist skepticism about moral narratives or theories, but the majority emphasis must be on ethical cognitivism, moral objectivity and Modernist love of overarching stories or narratives.

Immoral or wicked people want moral systems to be rejected and dismantled so they can be engage in wicked and immoral ways without being condemned, hindered or socially ridiculed. They want their immoral actions and choices allowed, tolerated, and perhaps popularized as moral choices whose bracketing is privileged only by the individual actor or his clique—only that individual and his gang can label an action moral or immoral, and any action which they characterize as good is good, not matter its normative status in objective reality.

Moral narratives are cardinal and mandatory. They are fitting, proper, relevant to moral practice and are conceptually productive generalized guides to human behavior and need be binding on an entire people, for that is what God is doing with the Ten Commandments.

These theories provide relief and assistance for people, real help. To some, every person is peerless, and their moral challenges are somewhat singular. But more often, to perhaps to a larger extent, their problems fit within universal moral guidelines, so ethical theories can provide through practical reasoning applicable answers over.

The individualism is less centered in the subjectivity claim that each life and its moral dilemmas are so unique that others cannot understand it nor offer advice stemming from an ethical theory that is timely, relevant, and offering relief and a pathway to good choosing.

As individuators, people meet their individualism needs, applying universal moral principles by thinking more than feeling, but then ironically then the individual choices become more personal and customized as the individuator lives as an objective, existent avatar of the ideal individuating hero, the living angel.

Moral theories can cover most of the difficulties, exceptions borderline cases and concrete issues bedeviling people.

To believe in moral theories is to assert that we can have universal moral laws that govern and regulate human conduct, that we can judge people, their characters, actions and choices in meangiful, knowledgeable ways most of the time, though not all the time, that we need to be pro-life, pro-love- pro-God, pro-cosmos most of the time, that these vying and various ethical theories be blended in more or less emphases to form a personalized grand moral theory, with the idea that one promotes goodness in the will in line with fielding a good will, guided by God, so most of the time people can come to agree how to move forward.

We must live in the real world but our noble theory our moral grand narrative can be helpful more than not if we do not rigidly seek to impose it al specific people and particular cases.

 

Ethical theory is more useful than not. A theory gives us a rational model or guideline to test our potential choices and actions. Our moral theory provides us with a standard of beavhiro to live by.

There are universal moral scenarios that apply in most but not particular instances in human lives. It is usually not inapplicable. It is a recipe for action generally it is helpful more than not.

Our metaethical theory or presuppositions give us theoretical perspective so we have an rational framework with which to place a moral choice so we can quickly see the pros and cons to it

If we can set up a moral theory which most of a culture’s population—its majority--subscribe to and live by, then we can build a cultural story a civilization promoting social cohesion, where the masses share and affectionately, loyally live out their grand narrative: this engenders a harmonious peaceful society with law and order, coexistence and a way to resolve peacefully and legally disputes which arise.

As a moderate I propose that one blend together the perhaps contradictory, competing ethical theories, that ethical dialetheia and true contradictions; exist: pluralistically we are to blend them together.

Even if we just follow one moral theory, okay but be so as an egoist individuators, and that will give people a grand narrative in and of itself.

My version of virtue ethics: we are born evil so if learn to have a virtuous character or a good will we practice being good until we overcome our evil natures and have a good nature and a good will which is adopted, cultivated and unnatural but works.

A21: “On the other side, a quite different sort of question arises from seeking to give a metaphysical grounding for moral truths or for the claim that there are none. Supposing there are some moral truths, what makes them true? What account can be given of the truth-conditions of moral statements? Here arise familiar questions of moral skepticism and moral relativism; here, the idea of “a reason” is wielded by many hoping to defend a non-skeptical moral metaphysics (e.g., Smith 2013). The topic of moral reasoning lies in between these two other familiar topics in the following simple sense: moral reasoners operate with what they take to be morally true but, instead of asking what makes their moral beliefs true, they proceed responsibly to attempt to figure out what to do in light of those considerations. The philosophical study of moral reasoning concerns itself with the nature of these attempts.

These three topics clearly interrelate. Conceivably, the relations between them would be so tight as to rule out any independent interest in the topic of moral reasoning. For instance, if all that could usefully be said about moral reasoning were that it is a matter of attending to the moral facts, then all interest would devolve upon the question of what those facts are – with some residual focus on the idea of moral attention (McNaughton 1988). Alternatively, it might be thought that moral reasoning is simply a matter of applying the correct moral theory via ordinary modes of deductive and empirical reasoning. Again, if that were true, one’s sufficient goal would be to find that theory and get the non-moral facts right. Neither of these reductive extremes seems plausible, however. Take the potential reduction to getting the facts right, first.

Contemporary advocates of the importance of correctly perceiving the morally relevant facts tend to focus on facts that we can perceive using our ordinary sense faculties and our ordinary capacities of recognition, such as that this person has an infection or that this person needs my medical help. On such a footing, it is possible to launch powerful arguments against the claim that moral principles undergird every moral truth (Dancy 1993) and for the claim that we can sometimes perfectly well decide what to do by acting on the reasons we perceive instinctively – or as we have been trained – without engaging in any moral reasoning. Yet this is not a sound footing for arguing that moral reasoning, beyond simply attending to the moral facts, is always unnecessary. On the contrary, we often find ourselves facing novel perplexities and moral conflicts in which our moral perception is an inadequate guide.”

My response: I am not an epistemological dogmatist, that moral principles undergird every moral proposition, but the noncognitivists and sentimentalists either cynically or unintentionally seek to and do grow evil in the world, when they deny that general acceptance of and adherence to a moral theory—any reasonable moral theory--undergirds the great majority of human chocies, and we can about 85% of the time identify what is evil and what is good.

A21: “In addressing the moral questions surrounding whether society ought to enforce surrogate-motherhood contracts, for instance, the scientific and technological novelties involved make our moral perceptions unreliable and shaky guides. When a medical researcher who has noted an individual’s illness also notes the fact that diverting resources to caring, clinically, for this individual would inhibit the progress of my research, thus harming the long-term health chances of future sufferers of this illness, he or she comes face to face with conflicting moral considerations. At this juncture, it is far less plausible or satisfying simply to say that, employing one’s ordinary sensory and recognitional capacities, one sees what is to be done, both things considered. To posit a special faculty of moral intuition that generates such overall judgments in the face of conflicting considerations is to wheel in a deus ex machina. It cuts inquiry short in a way that serves the purposes of fiction better than it serves the purposes of understanding. It is plausible instead to suppose that moral reasoning comes in at this point (Campbell & Kumar 2012).

For present purposes, it is worth noting, David Hume and the moral sense theorists do not count as short-circuiting our understanding of moral reasoning in this way. It is true that Hume presents himself, especially in the Treatise of Human Nature, as a disbeliever in any specifically practical or moral reasoning. In doing so, however, he employs an exceedingly narrow definition of “reasoning” (Hume 2000, Book I, Part iii, sect. ii). For present purposes, by contrast, we are using a broader working gloss of “reasoning,” one not controlled by an ambition to parse out the relative contributions of (the faculty of) reason and of the passions. And about moral reasoning in this broader sense, as responsible thinking about what one ought to do, Hume has many interesting things to say, starting with the thought that moral reasoning must involve a double correction of perspective (see section 2.4) adequately to account for the claims of other people and of the farther future, a double correction that is accomplished with the aid of the so-called “calm passions.””

My response: Moral reasoning or practical reasoning should guide our moral choices, but if we feel or intuitively sense (should that intuition be rational, conceptual, and linguistically expressible, or is just a nonverbal, felt, reaction of approval or disapproval to what we have encountered or experienced), strongly, that moral sensation should be taken seriously, perhaps as the decisive conscious reaction to a potential action.

A21: “If we turn from the possibility that perceiving the facts aright will displace moral reasoning to the possibility that applying the correct moral theory will displace – or exhaust – moral reasoning, there are again reasons to be skeptical. One reason is that moral theories do not arise in a vacuum; instead, they develop against a broad backdrop of moral convictions. Insofar as the first potentially reductive strand, emphasizing the importance of perceiving moral facts, has force – and it does have some – it also tends to show that moral theories need to gain support by systematizing or accounting for a wide range of moral facts (Sidgwick 1981). As in most other arenas in which theoretical explanation is called for, the degree of explanatory success will remain partial and open to improvement via revisions in the theory (see section 2.6). Unlike the natural sciences, however, moral theory is an endeavor that, as John Rawls once put it, is “Socratic” in that it is a subject pertaining to actions “shaped by self-examination” (Rawls 1971, 48f.). If this observation is correct, it suggests that the moral questions we set out to answer arise from our reflections about what matters. By the same token – and this is the present point – a moral theory is subject to being overturned because it generates concrete implications that do not sit well with us on due reflection. This being so, and granting the great complexity of the moral terrain, it seems highly unlikely that we will ever generate a moral theory on the basis of which we can serenely and confidently proceed in a deductive way to generate answers to what we ought to do in all concrete cases. This conclusion is reinforced by a second consideration, namely that insofar as a moral theory is faithful to the complexity of the moral phenomena, it will contain within it many possibilities for conflicts among its own elements. Even if it does deploy some priority rules, these are unlikely to be able to cover all contingencies. Hence, some moral reasoning that goes beyond the deductive application of the correct theory is bound to be needed.

In short, a sound understanding of moral reasoning will not take the form of reducing it to one of the other two levels of moral philosophy identified above. Neither the demand to attend to the moral facts nor the directive to apply the correct moral theory exhausts or sufficiently describes moral reasoning.

1.4 Gaining Moral Insight from Studying Moral Reasoning

In addition to posing philosophical problems in its own right, moral reasoning is of interest on account of its implications for moral facts and moral theories. Accordingly, attending to moral reasoning will often be useful to those whose real interest is in determining the right answer to some concrete moral problem or in arguing for or against some moral theory. The characteristic ways we attempt to work through a given sort of moral quandary can be just as revealing about our considered approaches to these matters as are any bottom-line judgments we may characteristically come to. Further, we may have firm, reflective convictions about how a given class of problems is best tackled, deliberatively, even when we remain in doubt about what should be done. In such cases, attending to the modes of moral reasoning that we characteristically accept can usefully expand the set of moral information from which we start, suggesting ways to structure the competing considerations.

Facts about the nature of moral inference and moral reasoning may have important direct implications for moral theory. For instance, it might be taken to be a condition of adequacy of any moral theory that it play a practically useful role in our efforts at self-understanding and deliberation. It should be deliberation-guiding (Richardson 2018, §1.2). If this condition is accepted, then any moral theory that would require agents to engage in abstruse or difficult reasoning may be inadequate for that reason, as would be any theory that assumes that ordinary individuals are generally unable to reason in the ways that the theory calls for. J.S. Mill (1979) conceded that we are generally unable to do the calculations called for by utilitarianism, as he understood it, and argued that we should be consoled by the fact that, over the course of history, experience has generated secondary principles that guide us well enough. Rather more dramatically, R. M. Hare defended utilitarianism as well capturing the reasoning of ideally informed and rational “archangels” (1981). Taking seriously a deliberation-guidance desideratum for moral theory would favor, instead, theories that more directly inform efforts at moral reasoning by we “proletarians,” to use Hare’s contrasting term.

Accordingly, the close relations between moral reasoning, the moral facts, and moral theory do not eliminate moral reasoning as a topic of interest. To the contrary, because moral reasoning has important implications about moral facts and moral theories, these close relations lend additional interest to the topic of moral reasoning.

1.5 How Distinct is Moral Reasoning from Practical Reasoning in General?

The final threshold question is whether moral reasoning is truly distinct from practical reasoning more generally understood. (The question of whether moral reasoning, even if practical, is structurally distinct from theoretical reasoning that simply proceeds from a proper recognition of the moral facts has already been implicitly addressed and answered, for the purposes of the present discussion, in the affirmative.) In addressing this final question, it is difficult to overlook the way different moral theories project quite different models of moral reasoning – again a link that might be pursued by the moral philosopher seeking leverage in either direction. For instance, Aristotle’s views might be as follows: a quite general account can be given of practical reasoning, which includes selecting means to ends and determining the constituents of a desired activity. The difference between the reasoning of a vicious person and that of a virtuous person differs not at all in its structure, but only in its content, for the virtuous person pursues true goods, whereas the vicious person simply gets side-tracked by apparent ones. To be sure, the virtuous person may be able to achieve a greater integration of his or her ends via practical reasoning (because of the way the various virtues cohere), but this is a difference in the result of practical reasoning and not in its structure. At an opposite extreme, Kant’s categorical imperative has been taken to generate an approach to practical reasoning (via a “typic of practical judgment”) that is distinctive from other practical reasoning both in the range of considerations it addresses and its structure (Nell 1975). Whereas prudential practical reasoning, on Kant’s view, aims to maximize one’s happiness, moral reasoning addresses the potential universalizability of the maxims – roughly, the intentions – on which one acts. Views intermediate between Aristotle’s and Kant’s in this respect include Hare’s utilitarian view and Aquinas’ natural-law view. On Hare’s view, just as an ideal prudential agent applies maximizing rationality to his or her own preferences, an ideal moral agent’s reasoning applies maximizing rationality to the set of everyone’s preferences that its archangelic capacity for sympathy has enabled it to internalize (Hare 1981). Thomistic, natural-law views share the Aristotelian view about the general unity of practical reasoning in pursuit of the good, rightly or wrongly conceived, but add that practical reason, in addition to demanding that we pursue the fundamental human goods, also, and distinctly, demands that we not attack these goods. In this way, natural-law views incorporate some distinctively moral structuring – such as the distinctions between doing and allowing and the so-called doctrine of double effect’s distinction between intending as a means and accepting as a by-product – within a unified account of practical reasoning (see entry on the natural law tradition in ethics). In light of this diversity of views about the relation between moral reasoning and practical or prudential reasoning, a general account of moral reasoning that does not want to presume the correctness of a definite moral theory will do well to remain agnostic on the question of how moral reasoning relates to non-moral practical reasoning.”

My response: It would seem obvious that one’s metaethical or theoretical moral reasoning should be  coherent and consistent with one moral choices, and as coherent and consistent as possible, with one’s practical moral reasoning to complete the selected action.

A21: “2. General Philosophical Questions about Moral Reasoning

To be sure, most great philosophers who have addressed the nature of moral reasoning were far from agnostic about the content of the correct moral theory, and developed their reflections about moral reasoning in support of or in derivation from their moral theory. Nonetheless, contemporary discussions that are somewhat agnostic about the content of moral theory have arisen around important and controversial aspects of moral reasoning. We may group these around the following seven questions:

  1. How do relevant considerations get taken up in moral reasoning?
  2. Is it essential to moral reasoning for the considerations it takes up to be crystallized into, or ranged under, principles?
  3. How do we sort out which moral considerations are most relevant?
  4. In what ways do motivational elements shape moral reasoning?
  5. What is the best way to model the kinds of conflicts among considerations that arise in moral reasoning?
  6. Does moral reasoning include learning from experience and changing one’s mind?
  7. How can we reason, morally, with one another?

The remainder of this article takes up these seven questions in turn.

2.1 Moral Uptake

One advantage to defining “reasoning” capaciously, as here, is that it helps one recognize that the processes whereby we come to be concretely aware of moral issues are integral to moral reasoning as it might more narrowly be understood. Recognizing moral issues when they arise requires a highly trained set of capacities and a broad range of emotional attunements. Philosophers of the moral sense school of the 17th and 18th centuries stressed innate emotional propensities, such as sympathy with other humans. Classically influenced virtue theorists, by contrast, give more importance to the training of perception and the emotional growth that must accompany it. Among contemporary philosophers working in empirical ethics there is a similar divide, with some arguing that we process situations using an innate moral grammar (Mikhail 2011) and some emphasizing the role of emotions in that processing (Haidt 2001, Prinz 2007, Greene 2014). For the moral reasoner, a crucial task for our capacities of moral recognition is to mark out certain features of a situation as being morally salient. Sartre’s student, for instance, focused on the competing claims of his mother and the Free French, giving them each an importance to his situation that he did not give to eating French cheese or wearing a uniform. To say that certain features are marked out as morally salient is not to imply that the features thus singled out answer to the terms of some general principle or other: we will come to the question of particularism, below. Rather, it is simply to say that recognitional attention must have a selective focus.

What will be counted as a moral issue or difficulty, in the sense requiring moral agents’ recognition, will again vary by moral theory. Not all moral theories would count filial loyalty and patriotism as moral duties. It is only at great cost, however, that any moral theory could claim to do without a layer of moral thinking involving situation-recognition. A calculative sort of utilitarianism, perhaps, might be imagined according to which there is no need to spot a moral issue or difficulty, as every choice node in life presents the agent with the same, utility-maximizing task. Perhaps Jeremy Bentham held a utilitarianism of this sort. For the more plausible utilitarianisms mentioned above, however, such as Mill’s and Hare’s, agents need not always calculate afresh, but must instead be alive to the possibility that because the ordinary “landmarks and direction posts” lead one astray in the situation at hand, they must make recourse to a more direct and critical mode of moral reasoning. Recognizing whether one is in one of those situations thus becomes the principal recognitional task for the utilitarian agent. (Whether this task can be suitably confined, of course, has long been one of the crucial questions about whether such indirect forms of utilitarianism, attractive on other grounds, can prevent themselves from collapsing into a more Benthamite, direct form: cf. Brandt 1979.)

Note that, as we have been describing moral uptake, we have not implied that what is perceived is ever a moral fact. Rather, it might be that what is perceived is some ordinary, descriptive feature of a situation that is, for whatever reason, morally relevant. An account of moral uptake will interestingly impinge upon the metaphysics of moral facts, however, if it holds that moral facts can be perceived. Importantly intermediate, in this respect, is the set of judgments involving so-called “thick” evaluative concepts – for example, that someone is callous, boorish, just, or brave (see the entry on thick ethical concepts). These do not invoke the supposedly “thinner” terms of overall moral assessment, “good,” or “right.” Yet they are not innocent of normative content, either. Plainly, we do recognize callousness when we see clear cases of it. Plainly, too – whatever the metaphysical implications of the last fact – our ability to describe our situations in these thick normative terms is crucial to our ability to reason morally.

It is debated how closely our abilities of moral discernment are tied to our moral motivations. For Aristotle and many of his ancient successors, the two are closely linked, in that someone not brought up into virtuous motivations will not see things correctly. For instance, cowards will overestimate dangers, the rash will underestimate them, and the virtuous will perceive them correctly (Eudemian Ethics 1229b23–27). By the Stoics, too, having the right motivations was regarded as intimately tied to perceiving the world correctly; but whereas Aristotle saw the emotions as allies to enlist in support of sound moral discernment, the Stoics saw them as inimical to clear perception of the truth (cf. Nussbaum 2001). “

My response: I approve of the author’s take that our moral discernment abilities are tied to our moral motivations, so the egoist will be more inclined to make sound morally sensed and morally reasoned discernments than the altruist.

A21:”2.2 Moral Principles

That one discerns features and qualities of some situation that are relevant to sizing it up morally does not yet imply that one explicitly or even implicitly employs any general claims in describing it. Perhaps all that one perceives are particularly embedded features and qualities, without saliently perceiving them as instantiations of any types. Sartre’s student may be focused on his mother and on the particular plights of several of his fellow Frenchmen under Nazi occupation, rather than on any purported requirements of filial duty or patriotism. Having become aware of some moral issue in such relatively particular terms, he might proceed directly to sorting out the conflict between them. Another possibility, however, and one that we frequently seem to exploit, is to formulate the issue in general terms: “An only child should stick by an otherwise isolated parent,” for instance, or “one should help those in dire need if one can do so without significant personal sacrifice.” Such general statements would be examples of “moral principles,” in a broad sense. (We do not here distinguish between principles and rules. those who do include Dworkin 1978 and Gert 1998.)

We must be careful, here, to distinguish the issue of whether principles commonly play an implicit or explicit role in moral reasoning, including well-conducted moral reasoning, from the issue of whether principles necessarily figure as part of the basis of moral truth. The latter issue is best understood as a metaphysical question about the nature and basis of moral facts. What is currently known as moral particularism is the view that there are no defensible moral principles and that moral reasons, or well-grounded moral facts, can exist independently of any basis in a general principle. A contrary view holds that moral reasons are necessarily general, whether because the sources of their justification are all general or because a moral claim is ill-formed if it contains particularities. But whether principles play a useful role in moral reasoning is certainly a different question from whether principles play a necessary role in accounting for the ultimate truth-conditions of moral statements. Moral particularism, as just defined, denies their latter role. Some moral particularists seem also to believe that moral particularism implies that moral principles cannot soundly play a useful role in reasoning. This claim is disputable, as it seems a contingent matter whether the relevant particular facts arrange themselves in ways susceptible to general summary and whether our cognitive apparatus can cope with them at all without employing general principles. Although the metaphysical controversy about moral particularism lies largely outside our topic, we will revisit it in section 2.5, in connection with the weighing of conflicting reasons.”

My response: I do not know if I am following this argument successfully, but my intuition as a moral theorist is that ethical theory and the moral principles which comprise it are important for moral reasoning, and we should be able to infer deductively guiding rules from such principles.

A21: “With regard to moral reasoning, while there are some self-styled “anti-theorists” who deny that abstract structures of linked generalities are important to moral reasoning (Clarke, et al. 1989), it is more common to find philosophers who recognize both some role for particular judgment and some role for moral principles. Thus, neo-Aristotelians like Nussbaum who emphasize the importance of “finely tuned and richly aware” particular discernment also regard that discernment as being guided by a set of generally describable virtues whose general descriptions will come into play in at least some kinds of cases (Nussbaum 1990). “Situation ethicists” of an earlier generation (e.g. Fletcher 1997) emphasized the importance of taking into account a wide range of circumstantial differentiae, but against the background of some general principles whose application the differentiae help sort out. Feminist ethicists influenced by Carol Gilligan’s path breaking work on moral development have stressed the moral centrality of the kind of care and discernment that are salient and well-developed by people immersed in particular relationships (Held 1995); but this emphasis is consistent with such general principles as “one ought to be sensitive to the wishes of one’s friends”(see the entry on feminist moral psychology). Again, if we distinguish the question of whether principles are useful in responsibly-conducted moral thinking from the question of whether moral reasons ultimately all derive from general principles, and concentrate our attention solely on the former, we will see that some of the opposition to general moral principles melts away.

It should be noted that we have been using a weak notion of generality, here. It is contrasted only with the kind of strict particularity that comes with indexicals and proper names. General statements or claims – ones that contain no such particular references – are not necessarily universal generalizations, making an assertion about all cases of the mentioned type. Thus, “one should normally help those in dire need” is a general principle, in this weak sense. Possibly, such logically loose principles would be obfuscatory in the context of an attempt to reconstruct the ultimate truth-conditions of moral statements. Such logically loose principles would clearly be useless in any attempt to generate a deductively tight “practical syllogism.” In our day-to-day, non-deductive reasoning, however, such logically loose principles appear to be quite useful. (Recall that we are understanding “reasoning” quite broadly, as responsibly conducted thinking: nothing in this understanding of reasoning suggests any uniquely privileged place for deductive inference: cf. Harman 1986. For more on defeasible or “default” principles, see section 2.5.)

In this terminology, establishing that general principles are essential to moral reasoning leaves open the further question whether logically tight, or exceptionless, principles are also essential to moral reasoning. Certainly, much of our actual moral reasoning seems to be driven by attempts to recast or reinterpret principles so that they can be taken to be exceptionless. Adherents and inheritors of the natural-law tradition in ethics (e.g. Donagan 1977) are particularly supple defenders of exceptionless moral principles, as they are able to avail themselves not only of a refined tradition of casuistry but also of a wide array of subtle – some would say overly subtle – distinctions, such as those mentioned above between doing and allowing and between intending as a means and accepting as a byproduct.

A related role for a strong form of generality in moral reasoning comes from the Kantian thought that one’s moral reasoning must counter one’s tendency to make exceptions for oneself. Accordingly, Kant holds, as we have noted, that we must ask whether the maxims of our actions can serve as universal laws. As most contemporary readers understand this demand, it requires that we engage in a kind of hypothetical generalization across agents, and ask about the implications of everybody acting that way in those circumstances. The grounds for developing Kant’s thought in this direction have been well explored (e.g., Nell 1975, Korsgaard 1996, Engstrom 2009). The importance and the difficulties of such a hypothetical generalization test in ethics were discussed the influential works Gibbard 1965 and Goldman 1974.

2.3 Sorting Out Which Considerations Are Most Relevant

Whether or not moral considerations need the backing of general principles, we must expect situations of action to present us with multiple moral considerations. In addition, of course, these situations will also present us with a lot of information that is not morally relevant. On any realistic account, a central task of moral reasoning is to sort out relevant considerations from irrelevant ones, as well as to determine which are especially relevant and which only slightly so. That a certain woman is Sartre’s student’s mother seems arguably to be a morally relevant fact; what about the fact (supposing it is one) that she has no other children to take care of her? Addressing the task of sorting what is morally relevant from what is not, some philosophers have offered general accounts of moral relevant features. Others have given accounts of how we sort out which of the relevant features are most relevant, a process of thinking that sometimes goes by the name of “casuistry.”

Before we look at ways of sorting out which features are morally relevant or most morally relevant, it may be useful to note a prior step taken by some casuists, which was to attempt to set out a schema that would capture all of the features of an action or proposed action. The Roman Catholic casuists of the middle ages did so by drawing on Aristotle’s categories. Accordingly, they asked, where, when, why, how, by what means, to whom, or by whom the action in question is to be done or avoided (see Jonsen and Toulmin 1988). The idea was that complete answers to these questions would contain all of the features of the action, of which the morally relevant ones would be a subset. Although metaphysically uninteresting, the idea of attempting to list all of an action’s features in this way represents a distinctive – and extreme – heuristic for moral reasoning.

Turning to the morally relevant features, one of the most developed accounts is Bernard Gert’s. He develops a list of features relevant to whether the violation of a moral rule should be generally allowed. Given the designed function of Gert’s list, it is natural that most of his morally relevant features make reference to the set of moral rules he defended. Accordingly, some of Gert’s distinctions between dimensions of relevant features reflect controversial stances in moral theory. For example, one of the dimensions is whether “the violation [is] done intentionally or only knowingly” (Gert 1998, 234) – a distinction that those who reject the doctrine of double effect would not find relevant.

In deliberating about what we ought, morally, to do, we also often attempt to figure out which considerations are most relevant. To take an issue mentioned above: Are surrogate motherhood contracts more akin to agreements with babysitters (clearly acceptable) or to agreements with prostitutes (not clearly so)? That is, which feature of surrogate motherhood is more relevant: that it involves a contract for child-care services or that it involves payment for the intimate use of the body? Both in such relatively novel cases and in more familiar ones, reasoning by analogy plays a large role in ordinary moral thinking. When this reasoning by analogy starts to become systematic – a social achievement that requires some historical stability and reflectiveness about what are taken to be moral norms – it begins to exploit comparison to cases that are “paradigmatic,” in the sense of being taken as settled. Within such a stable background, a system of casuistry can develop that lends some order to the appeal to analogous cases. To use an analogy: the availability of a widely accepted and systematic set of analogies and the availability of what are taken to be moral norms may stand to one another as chicken does to egg: each may startbe an indispensable moment in the genesis of the other.”

My response: Casuistry seems to be applying a generalized abstract principle to one moral act, and then generalizing it and applying it to another moral act, but there is a taint of corrupt rationalization to justify evil deeds which goes along with this.

It is better to morally reason from an act, make a generalization about it, and then by analogy apply that conclusion or theoretical reason to a new instance of behavior without all of this historical baggage, of warped moral reasoning, painting all theoretical moral reasoning a suspect as it surely is not?

A21: “Casuistry, thus understood, is an indispensable aid to moral reasoning. At least, that it is would follow from conjoining two features of the human moral situation mentioned above: the multifariousness of moral considerations that arise in particular cases and the need and possibility for employing moral principles in sound moral reasoning. We require moral judgment, not simply a deductive application of principles or a particularist bottom-line intuition about what we should do. This judgment must be responsible to moral principles yet cannot be straightforwardly derived from them. Accordingly, our moral judgment is greatly aided if it is able to rest on the sort of heuristic support that casuistry offers. Thinking through which of two analogous cases provides a better key to understanding the case at hand is a useful way of organizing our moral reasoning, and one on which we must continue to depend. If we lack the kind of broad consensus on a set of paradigm cases on which the Renaissance Catholic or Talmudic casuists could draw, our casuistic efforts will necessarily be more controversial and tentative than theirs; but we are not wholly without settled cases from which to work. Indeed, as Jonsen and Toulmin suggest at the outset of their thorough explanation and defense of casuistry, the depth of disagreement about moral theories that characterizes a pluralist society may leave us having to rest comparatively more weight on the cases about which we can find agreement than did the classic casuists (Jonsen and Toulmin 1988).”

My response I know very little about casuistry, but if this analytical framework of studying a problem and framing an analogous or different moral problem in light of his framework might make this heuristic applied method useful, instructive and illuminating. Compare/ contrast excises are often helpful.

A21: “Despite the long history of casuistry, there is little that can usefully be said about how one ought to reason about competing analogies. In the law, where previous cases have precedential importance, more can be said. As Sunstein notes (Sunstein 1996, chap. 3), the law deals with particular cases, which are always “potentially distinguishable” (72); yet the law also imposes “a requirement of practical consistency” (67). This combination of features makes reasoning by analogy particularly influential in the law, for one must decide whether a given case is more like one set of precedents or more like another. Since the law must proceed even within a pluralist society such as ours, Sunstein argues, we see that analogical reasoning can go forward on the basis of “incompletely theorized judgments” or of what Rawls calls an “overlapping consensus” (Rawls 1996). That is, although a robust use of analogous cases depends, as we have noted, on some shared background agreement, this agreement need not extend to all matters or all levels of individuals’ moral thinking. Accordingly, although in a pluralist society we may lack the kind of comprehensive normative agreement that made the high casuistry of Renaissance Christianity possible, the path of the law suggests that normatively forceful, case-based, analogical reasoning can still go on. A modern, competing approach to case-based or precedent-respecting reasoning has been developed by John F. Horty (2016). On Horty’s approach, which builds on the default logic developed in (Horty 2012), the body of precedent systematically shifts the weights of the reasons arising in a new case.

Reasoning by appeal to cases is also a favorite mode of some recent moral philosophers. Since our focus here is not on the methods of moral theory, we do not need to go into any detail in comparing different ways in which philosophers wield cases for and against alternative moral theories. There is, however, an important and broadly applicable point worth making about ordinary reasoning by reference to cases that emerges most clearly from the philosophical use of such reasoning. Philosophers often feel free to imagine cases, often quite unlikely ones, in order to attempt to isolate relevant differences. An infamous example is a pair of cases offered by James Rachels to cast doubt on the moral significance of the distinction between killing and letting die, here slightly redescribed. In both cases, there is at the outset a boy in a bathtub and a greedy older cousin downstairs who will inherit the family manse if and only if the boy predeceases him (Rachels 1975). In Case A, the cousin hears a thump, runs up to find the boy unconscious in the bath, and reaches out to turn on the tap so that the water will rise up to drown the boy. In Case B, the cousin hears a thump, runs up to find the boy unconscious in the bath with the water running, and decides to sit back and do nothing until the boy drowns. Since there is surely no moral difference between these cases, Rachels argued, the general distinction between killing and letting die is undercut. “Not so fast!” is the well-justified reaction (cf. Beauchamp 1979). Just because a factor is morally relevant in a certain way in comparing one pair of cases does not mean that it either is or must be relevant in the same way or to the same degree when comparing other cases. Shelly Kagan has dubbed the failure to take account of this fact of contextual interaction when wielding comparison cases the “additive fallacy” (1988). Kagan concludes from this that the reasoning of moral theorists must depend upon some theory that helps us anticipate and account for ways in which factors will interact in various contexts. A parallel lesson, reinforcing what we have already observed in connection with casuistry proper, would apply for moral reasoning in general: reasoning from cases must at least implicitly rely upon a set of organizing judgments or beliefs, of a kind that would, on some understandings, count as a moral “theory.” If this is correct, it provides another kind of reason to think that moral considerations could be crystallized into principles that make manifest the organizing structure involved.

2.4 Moral Reasoning and Moral Psychology

We are concerned here with moral reasoning as a species of practical reasoning – reasoning directed to deciding what to do and, if successful, issuing in an intention. But how can such practical reasoning succeed? How can moral reasoning hook up with motivationally effective psychological states so as to have this kind of causal effect? “Moral psychology” – the traditional name for the philosophical study of intention and action – has a lot to say to such questions, both in its traditional, a priori form and its newly popular empirical form. In addition, the conclusions of moral psychology can have substantive moral implications, for it may be reasonable to assume that if there are deep reasons that a given type of moral reasoning cannot be practical, then any principles that demand such reasoning are unsound. In this spirit, Samuel Scheffler has explored “the importance for moral philosophy of some tolerably realistic understanding of human motivational psychology” (Scheffler 1992, 8) and Peter Railton has developed the idea that certain moral principles might generate a kind of “alienation” (Railton 1984). In short, we may be interested in what makes practical reasoning of a certain sort psychologically possible both for its own sake and as a way of working out some of the content of moral theory. “

My response: If moral reasoning is practical reasoning (applied ethics use), then theoretical reasoning is needed too to be rounded to guarantee that what the actor intended  is effectiveand if he acted to complete his intention is ethically and situationally relevant.

A21: “The issue of psychological possibility is an important one for all kinds of practical reasoning (cf. Audi 1989). In morality, it is especially pressing, as morality often asks individuals to depart from satisfying their own interests. As a result, it may appear that moral reasoning’s practical effect could not be explained by a simple appeal to the initial motivations that shape or constitute someone’s interests, in combination with a requirement, like that mentioned above, to will the necessary means to one’s ends. Morality, it may seem, instead requires individuals to act on ends that may not be part of their “motivational set,” in the terminology of Williams 1981. How can moral reasoning lead people to do that? The question is a traditional one. Plato’s Republic answered that the appearances are deceiving, and that acting morally is, in fact, in the enlightened self-interest of the agent. Kant, in stark contrast, held that our transcendent capacity to act on our conception of a practical law enables us to set ends and to follow morality even when doing so sharply conflicts with our interests. Many other answers have been given. In recent times, philosophers have defended what has been called “internalism” about morality, which claims that there is a necessary conceptual link between agents’ moral judgment and their motivation. Michael Smith, for instance, puts the claim as follows (Smith 1994, 61):

If an agent judges that it is right for her to Φ in circumstances C, then either she is motivated to Φ in C or she is practically irrational.”

 

My response: I am not understanding or following the argument well at this point, but it seems to me that our moral judgment, based in deciding based on one’s moral reasoning and feelings, judges in line with one’s motivation, be it self-centered or other-centered, good or evil.

 

Generally,  one’s motivation will run parallel to one’s will, a kindly motivation will emanate from a good will, and that brings about moral judgements. If one’s motivation is cruel, sadistic or power-grasping, then it is in line with one’s bad will, and will be reflected as one makes immoral judgements.

A21: “Even this defeasible version of moral judgment internalism may be too strong; but instead of pursuing this issue further, let us turn to a question more internal to moral reasoning. (For more on the issue of moral judgment internalism, see moral motivation.)

The traditional question we were just glancing at picks up when moral reasoning is done. Supposing that we have some moral conclusion, it asks how agents can be motivated to go along with it. A different question about the intersection of moral reasoning and moral psychology, one more immanent to the former, concerns how motivational elements shape the reasoning process itself.

A powerful philosophical picture of human psychology, stemming from Hume, insists that beliefs and desires are distinct existences (Hume 2000, Book II, part iii, sect. iii; cf. Smith 1994, 7). This means that there is always a potential problem about how reasoning, which seems to work by concatenating beliefs, links up to the motivations that desire provides. The paradigmatic link is that of instrumental action: the desire to Ψ links with the belief that by Φing in circumstances C one will Ψ. Accordingly, philosophers who have examined moral reasoning within an essentially Humean, belief-desire psychology have sometimes accepted a constrained account of moral reasoning. Hume’s own account exemplifies the sort of constraint that is involved. As Hume has it, the calm passions support the dual correction of perspective constitutive of morality, alluded to above. Since these calm passions are seen as competing with our other passions in essentially the same motivational coinage, as it were, our passions limit the reach of moral reasoning.”

My response: Again, it seems obvious to me that moral beliefs can and often do conflict with our base desires. As moral, virtuous adults of self-love and good will, our moral reasoning must lead to action conclusions and choices chosen which match those action conclusions, and our motivation and desires must be made to come into line with moral choices consistent with having and maintaining our good will and good reputation. Base desires which we seek to fulfill cannot be our moral motivation and then lead to moral judgments to match those base desires and motivation.

A21: “An important step away from a narrow understanding of Humean moral psychology is taken if one recognizes the existence of what Rawls has called “principle-dependent desires” (Rawls 1996, 82–83; Rawls 2000, 46–47). These are desires whose objects cannot be characterized without reference to some rational or moral principle. An important special case of these is that of “conception-dependent desires,” in which the principle-dependent desire in question is seen by the agent as belonging to a broader conception, and as important on that account (Rawls 1996, 83–84; Rawls 2000, 148–152). For instance, conceiving of oneself as a citizen, one may desire to bear one’s fair share of society’s burdens. Although it may look like any content, including this, may substitute for Ψ in the Humean conception of desire, and although Hume set out to show how moral sentiments such as pride could be explained in terms of simple psychological mechanisms, his influential empiricism actually tends to restrict the possible content of desires. Introducing principle-dependent desires thus seems to mark a departure from a Humean psychology. As Rawls remarks, if “we may find ourselves drawn to the conceptions and ideals that both the right and the good express … , [h]ow is one to fix limits on what people might be moved by in thought and deliberation and hence may act from?” (1996, 85). While Rawls developed this point by contrasting Hume’s moral psychology with Kant’s, the same basic point is also made by neo-Aristotelians (e.g., McDowell 1998).

The introduction of principle-dependent desires bursts any would-be naturalist limit on their content; nonetheless, some philosophers hold that this notion remains too beholden to an essentially Humean picture to be able to capture the idea of a moral commitment. Desires, it may seem, remain motivational items that compete on the basis of strength. Saying that one’s desire to be just may be outweighed by one’s desire for advancement may seem to fail to capture the thought that one has a commitment – even a non-absolute one – to justice. Sartre designed his example of the student torn between staying with his mother and going to fight with the Free French so as to make it seem implausible that he ought to decide simply by determining which he more strongly wanted to do.

One way to get at the idea of commitment is to emphasize our capacity to reflect about what we want. By this route, one might distinguish, in the fashion of Harry Frankfurt, between the strength of our desires and “the importance of what we care about” (Frankfurt 1988). Although this idea is evocative, it provides relatively little insight into how it is that we thus reflect. Another way to model commitment is to take it that our intentions operate at a level distinct from our desires, structuring what we are willing to reconsider at any point in our deliberations (e.g. Bratman 1999). While this two-level approach offers some advantages, it is limited by its concession of a kind of normative primacy to the unreconstructed desires at the unreflective level. A more integrated approach might model the psychology of commitment in a way that reconceives the nature of desire from the ground up. One attractive possibility is to return to the Aristotelian conception of desire as being for the sake of some good or apparent good (cf. Richardson 2004). On this conception, the end for the sake of which an action is done plays an important regulating role, indicating, in part, what one will not do (Richardson 2018, §§8.3–8.4). Reasoning about final ends accordingly has a distinctive character (see Richardson 1994, Schmidtz 1995). Whatever the best philosophical account of the notion of a commitment – for another alternative, see (Tiberius 2000) – much of our moral reasoning does seem to involve expressions of and challenges to our commitments (Anderson and Pildes 2000).

Recent experimental work, employing both survey instruments and brain imaging technologies, has allowed philosophers to approach questions about the psychological basis of moral reasoning from novel angles. The initial brain data seems to show that individuals with damage to the pre-frontal lobes tend to reason in more straightforwardly consequentialist fashion than those without such damage (Koenigs et al. 2007). Some theorists take this finding as tending to confirm that fully competent human moral reasoning goes beyond a simple weighing of pros and cons to include assessment of moral constraints (e.g., Wellman & Miller 2008, Young & Saxe 2008). Others, however, have argued that the emotional responses of the prefrontal lobes interfere with the more sober and sound, consequentialist-style reasoning of the other parts of the brain (e.g. Greene 2014). The survey data reveals or confirms, among other things, interesting, normatively loaded asymmetries in our attribution of such concepts as responsibility and causality (Knobe 2006). It also reveals that many of moral theory’s most subtle distinctions, such as the distinction between an intended means and a foreseen side-effect, are deeply built into our psychologies, being present cross-culturally and in young children, in a way that suggests to some the possibility of an innate “moral grammar” (Mikhail 2011).

A final question about the connection between moral motivation and moral reasoning is whether someone without the right motivational commitments can reason well, morally. On Hume’s official, narrow conception of reasoning, which essentially limits it to tracing empirical and logical connections, the answer would be yes. The vicious person could trace the causal and logical implications of acting in a certain way just as a virtuous person could. The only difference would be practical, not rational: the two would not act in the same way. Note, however, that the Humean’s affirmative answer depends on departing from the working definition of “moral reasoning” used in this article, which casts it as a species of practical reasoning. Interestingly, Kant can answer “yes” while still casting moral reasoning as practical. On his view in the Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason, reasoning well, morally, does not depend on any prior motivational commitment, yet remains practical reasoning. That is because he thinks the moral law can itself generate motivation. (Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals and Religion offer a more complex psychology.) For Aristotle, by contrast, an agent whose motivations are not virtuously constituted will systematically misperceive what is good and what is bad, and hence will be unable to reason excellently. The best reasoning that a vicious person is capable of, according to Aristotle, is a defective simulacrum of practical wisdom that he calls “cleverness” (Nicomachean Ethics 1144a25).

2.5 Modeling Conflicting Moral Considerations

Moral considerations often conflict with one another. So do moral principles and moral commitments. Assuming that filial loyalty and patriotism are moral considerations, then Sartre’s student faces a moral conflict. Recall that it is one thing to model the metaphysics of morality or the truth conditions of moral statements and another to give an account of moral reasoning. In now looking at conflicting considerations, our interest here remains with the latter and not the former. Our principal interest is in ways that we need to structure or think about conflicting considerations in order to negotiate well our reasoning involving them.

One influential building-block for thinking about moral conflicts is W. D. Ross’s notion of a “prima facie duty”. Although this term misleadingly suggests mere appearance – the way things seem at first glance – it has stuck. Some moral philosophers prefer the term “pro tanto duty” (e.g., Hurley 1989). Ross explained that his term provides “a brief way of referring to the characteristic (quite distinct from that of being a duty proper) which an act has, in virtue of being of a certain kind (e.g., the keeping of a promise), of being an act which would be a duty proper if it were not at the same time of another kind which is morally significant.” Illustrating the point, he noted that a prima facie duty to keep a promise can be overridden by a prima facie duty to avert a serious accident, resulting in a proper, or unqualified, duty to do the latter (Ross 1988, 18–19). Ross described each prima facie duty as a “parti-resultant” attribute, grounded or explained by one aspect of an act, whereas “being one’s [actual] duty” is a “toti-resultant” attribute resulting from all such aspects of an act, taken together (28; see Pietroski 1993). This suggests that in each case there is, in principle, some function that generally maps from the partial contributions of each prima facie duty to some actual duty. What might that function be? To Ross’s credit, he writes that “for the estimation of the comparative stringency of these prima facie obligations no general rules can, so far as I can see, be laid down” (41). Accordingly, a second strand in Ross simply emphasizes, following Aristotle, the need for practical judgment by those who have been brought up into virtue (42).

How might considerations of the sort constituted by prima facie duties enter our moral reasoning? They might do so explicitly, or only implicitly. There is also a third, still weaker possibility (Scheffler 1992, 32): it might simply be the case that if the agent had recognized a prima facie duty, he would have acted on it unless he considered it to be overridden. This is a fact about how he would have reasoned.

Despite Ross’s denial that there is any general method for estimating the comparative stringency of prima facie duties, there is a further strand in his exposition that many find irresistible and that tends to undercut this denial. In the very same paragraph in which he states that he sees no general rules for dealing with conflicts, he speaks in terms of “the greatest balance of prima facie rightness.” This language, together with the idea of “comparative stringency,” ineluctably suggests the idea that the mapping function might be the same in each case of conflict and that it might be a quantitative one. On this conception, if there is a conflict between two prima facie duties, the one that is strongest in the circumstances should be taken to win. Duly cautioned about the additive fallacy (see section 2.3), we might recognize that the strength of a moral consideration in one set of circumstances cannot be inferred from its strength in other circumstances. Hence, this approach will need still to rely on intuitive judgments in many cases. But this intuitive judgment will be about which prima facie consideration is stronger in the circumstances, not simply about what ought to be done.

The thought that our moral reasoning either requires or is benefited by a virtual quantitative crutch of this kind has a long pedigree. Can we really reason well morally in a way that boils down to assessing the weights of the competing considerations? Addressing this question will require an excursus on the nature of moral reasons. Philosophical support for this possibility involves an idea of practical commensurability. We need to distinguish, here, two kinds of practical commensurability or incommensurability, one defined in metaphysical terms and one in deliberative terms. Each of these forms might be stated evaluatively or deontically. The first, metaphysical sort of value incommensurability is defined directly in terms of what is the case. Thus, to state an evaluative version: two values are metaphysically incommensurable just in case neither is better than the other nor are they equally good (see Chang 1998). Now, the metaphysical incommensurability of values, or its absence, is only loosely linked to how it would be reasonable to deliberate. If all values or moral considerations are metaphysically (that is, in fact) commensurable, still it might well be the case that our access to the ultimate commensurating function is so limited that we would fare ill by proceeding in our deliberations to try to think about which outcomes are “better” or which considerations are “stronger.” We might have no clue about how to measure the relevant “strength.” Conversely, even if metaphysical value incommensurability is common, we might do well, deliberatively, to proceed as if this were not the case, just as we proceed in thermodynamics as if the gas laws obtained in their idealized form. Hence, in thinking about the deliberative implications of incommensurable values, we would do well to think in terms of a definition tailored to the deliberative context. Start with a local, pairwise form. We may say that two options, A and B, are deliberatively commensurable just in case there is some one dimension of value in terms of which, prior to – or logically independently of – choosing between them, it is possible adequately to represent the force of the considerations bearing on the choice.

Philosophers as diverse as Immanuel Kant and John Stuart Mill have argued that unless two options are deliberatively commensurable, in this sense, it is impossible to choose rationally between them. Interestingly, Kant limited this claim to the domain of prudential considerations, recognizing moral reasoning as invoking considerations incommensurable with those of prudence. For Mill, this claim formed an important part of his argument that there must be some one, ultimate “umpire” principle – namely, on his view, the principle of utility. Henry Sidgwick elaborated Mill’s argument and helpfully made explicit its crucial assumption, which he called the “principle of superior validity” (Sidgwick 1981; cf. Schneewind 1977). This is the principle that conflict between distinct moral or practical considerations can be rationally resolved only on the basis of some third principle or consideration that is both more general and more firmly warranted than the two initial competitors. From this assumption, one can readily build an argument for the rational necessity not merely of local deliberative commensurability, but of a global deliberative commensurability that, like Mill and Sidgwick, accepts just one ultimate umpire principle (cf. Richardson 1994, chap. 6).

Sidgwick’s explicitness, here, is valuable also in helping one see how to resist the demand for deliberative commensurability. Deliberative commensurability is not necessary for proceeding rationally if conflicting considerations can be rationally dealt with in a holistic way that does not involve the appeal to a principle of “superior validity.” That our moral reasoning can proceed holistically is strongly affirmed by Rawls. Rawls’s characterizations of the influential ideal of reflective equilibrium and his related ideas about the nature of justification imply that we can deal with conflicting considerations in less hierarchical ways than imagined by Mill or Sidgwick. Instead of proceeding up a ladder of appeal to some highest court or supreme umpire, Rawls suggests, when we face conflicting considerations “we work from both ends” (Rawls 1999, 18). Sometimes indeed we revise our more particular judgments in light of some general principle to which we adhere; but we are also free to revise more general principles in light of some relatively concrete considered judgment. On this picture, there is no necessary correlation between degree of generality and strength of authority or warrant. That this holistic way of proceeding (whether in building moral theory or in deliberating: cf. Hurley 1989) can be rational is confirmed by the possibility of a form of justification that is similarly holistic: “justification is a matter of the mutual support of many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent view” (Rawls 1999, 19, 507). (Note that this statement, which expresses a necessary aspect of moral or practical justification, should not be taken as a definition or analysis thereof.) So there is an alternative to depending, deliberatively, on finding a dimension in terms of which considerations can be ranked as “stronger” or “better” or “more stringent”: one can instead “prune and adjust” with an eye to building more mutual support among the considerations that one endorses on due reflection. If even the desideratum of practical coherence is subject to such re-specification, then this holistic possibility really does represent an alternative to commensuration, as the deliberator, and not some coherence standard, retains reflective sovereignty (Richardson 1994, sec. 26). The result can be one in which the originally competing considerations are not so much compared as transformed (Richardson 2018, chap. 1)

Suppose that we start with a set of first-order moral considerations that are all commensurable as a matter of ultimate, metaphysical fact, but that our grasp of the actual strength of these considerations is quite poor and subject to systematic distortions. Perhaps some people are much better placed than others to appreciate certain considerations, and perhaps our strategic interactions would cause us to reach suboptimal outcomes if we each pursued our own unfettered judgment of how the overall set of considerations plays out. In such circumstances, there is a strong case for departing from maximizing reasoning without swinging all the way to the holist alternative. This case has been influentially articulated by Joseph Raz, who develops the notion of an “exclusionary reason” to occupy this middle position (Raz 1990).

“An exclusionary reason,” in Raz’s terminology, “is a second order reason to refrain from acting for some reason” (39). A simple example is that of Ann, who is tired after a long and stressful day, and hence has reason not to act on her best assessment of the reasons bearing on a particularly important investment decision that she immediately faces (37). This notion of an exclusionary reason allowed Raz to capture many of the complexities of our moral reasoning, especially as it involves principled commitments, while conceding that, at the first order, all practical reasons might be commensurable. Raz’s early strategy for reconciling commensurability with complexity of structure was to limit the claim that reasons are comparable with regard to strength to reasons of a given order. First-order reasons compete on the basis of strength; but conflicts between first- and second-order reasons “are resolved not by the strength of the competing reasons but by a general principle of practical reasoning which determines that exclusionary reasons always prevail” (40).

If we take for granted this “general principle of practical reasoning,” why should we recognize the existence of any exclusionary reasons, which by definition prevail independently of any contest of strength? Raz’s principal answer to this question shifts from the metaphysical domain of the strengths that various reasons “have” to the epistemically limited viewpoint of the deliberator. As in Ann’s case, we can see in certain contexts that a deliberator is likely to get things wrong if he or she acts on his or her perception of the first-order reasons. Second-order reasons indicate, with respect to a certain range of first-order reasons, that the agent “must not act for those reasons” (185). The broader justification of an exclusionary reason, then, can consistently be put in terms of the commensurable first-order reasons. Such a justification can have the following form: “Given this agent’s deliberative limitations, the balance of first-order reasons will likely be better conformed with if he or she refrains from acting for certain of those reasons.”

Raz’s account of exclusionary reasons might be used to reconcile ultimate commensurability with the structured complexity of our moral reasoning. Whether such an attempt could succeed would depend, in part, on the extent to which we have an actual grasp of first-order reasons, conflict among which can be settled solely on the basis of their comparative strength. Our consideration, above, of casuistry, the additive fallacy, and deliberative incommensurability may combine to make it seem that only in rare pockets of our practice do we have a good grasp of first-order reasons, if these are defined, à la Raz, as competing only in terms of strength. If that is right, then we will almost always have good exclusionary reasons to reason on some other basis than in terms of the relative strength of first-order reasons. Under those assumptions, the middle way that Raz’s idea of exclusionary reasons seems to open up would more closely approach the holist’s.

The notion of a moral consideration’s “strength,” whether put forward as part of a metaphysical picture of how first-order considerations interact in fact or as a suggestion about how to go about resolving a moral conflict, should not be confused with the bottom-line determination of whether one consideration, and specifically one duty, overrides another. In Ross’s example of conflicting prima facie duties, someone must choose between averting a serious accident and keeping a promise to meet someone. (Ross chose the case to illustrate that an “imperfect” duty, or a duty of commission, can override a strict, prohibitive duty.) Ross’s assumption is that all well brought-up people would agree, in this case, that the duty to avert serious harm to someone overrides the duty to keep such a promise. We may take it, if we like, that this judgment implies that we consider the duty to save a life, here, to be stronger than the duty to keep the promise; but in fact this claim about relative strength adds nothing to our understanding of the situation. Yet we do not reach our practical conclusion in this case by determining that the duty to save the boy’s life is stronger. The statement that this duty is here stronger is simply a way to embellish the conclusion that of the two prima facie duties that here conflict, it is the one that states the all-things-considered duty. To be “overridden” is just to be a prima facie duty that fails to generate an actual duty because another prima facie duty that conflicts with it – or several of them that do – does generate an actual duty. Hence, the judgment that some duties override others can be understood just in terms of their deontic upshots and without reference to considerations of strength. To confirm this, note that we can say, “As a matter of fidelity, we ought to keep the promise; as a matter of beneficence, we ought to save the life; we cannot do both; and both categories considered we ought to save the life.”

Understanding the notion of one duty overriding another in this way puts us in a position to take up the topic of moral dilemmas. Since this topic is covered in a separate article, here we may simply take up one attractive definition of a moral dilemma. Sinnott-Armstrong (1988) suggested that a moral dilemma is a situation in which the following are true of a single agent:

  1. He ought to do A.
  2. He ought to do B.
  3. He cannot do both A and B.
  4. (1) does not override (2) and (2) does not override (1).

This way of defining moral dilemmas distinguishes them from the kind of moral conflict, such as Ross’s promise-keeping/accident-prevention case, in which one of the duties is overridden by the other. Arguably, Sartre’s student faces a moral dilemma. Making sense of a situation in which neither of two duties overrides the other is easier if deliberative commensurability is denied. Whether moral dilemmas are possible will depend crucially on whether “ought” implies “can” and whether any pair of duties such as those comprised by (1) and (2) implies a single, “agglomerated” duty that the agent do both A and B. If either of these purported principles of the logic of duties is false, then moral dilemmas are possible.

Jonathan Dancy has well highlighted a kind of contextual variability in moral reasons that has come to be known as “reasons holism”: “a feature that is a reason in one case may be no reason at all, or an opposite reason, in another” (Dancy 2004). To adapt one of his examples: while there is often moral reason not to lie, when playing liar’s poker one generally ought to lie; otherwise, one will spoil the game (cf. Dancy 1993, 61). Dancy argues that reasons holism supports moral particularism of the kind discussed in section 2.2, according to which there are no defensible moral principles. Taking this conclusion seriously would radically affect how we conducted our moral reasoning. The argument’s premise of holism has been challenged (e.g., Audi 2004, McKeever & Ridge 2006). Philosophers have also challenged the inference from reasons holism to particularism in various ways. Mark Lance and Margaret Olivia Little (2007) have done so by exhibiting how defeasible generalizations, in ethics and elsewhere, depend systematically on context. We can work with them, they suggest, by utilizing a skill that is similar to the skill of discerning morally salient considerations, namely the skill of discerning relevant similarities among possible worlds. More generally, John F. Horty has developed a logical and semantic account according to which reasons are defaults and so behave holistically, but there are nonetheless general principles that explain how they behave (Horty 2012). And Mark Schroeder has argued that our holistic views about reasons are actually better explained by supposing that there are general principles (Schroeder 2011).

This excursus on moral reasons suggests that there are a number of good reasons why reasoning about moral matters might not simply reduce to assessing the weights of competing considerations.

2.6 Moral Learning and the Revision of Moral Views

If we have any moral knowledge, whether concerning general moral principles or concrete moral conclusions, it is surely very imperfect. What moral knowledge we are capable of will depend, in part, on what sorts of moral reasoning we are capable of. Although some moral learning may result from the theoretical work of moral philosophers and theorists, much of what we learn with regard to morality surely arises in the practical context of deliberation about new and difficult cases. This deliberation might be merely instrumental, concerned only with settling on means to moral ends, or it might be concerned with settling those ends. There is no special problem about learning what conduces to morally obligatory ends: that is an ordinary matter of empirical learning. But by what sorts of process can we learn which ends are morally obligatory, or which norms morally required? And, more specifically, is strictly moral learning possible via moral reasoning?

Much of what was said above with regard to moral uptake applies again in this context, with approximately the same degree of dubiousness or persuasiveness. If there is a role for moral perception or for emotions in agents’ becoming aware of moral considerations, these may function also to guide agents to new conclusions. For instance, it is conceivable that our capacity for outrage is a relatively reliable detector of wrong actions, even novel ones, or that our capacity for pleasure is a reliable detector of actions worth doing, even novel ones. (For a thorough defense of the latter possibility, which intriguingly interprets pleasure as a judgment of value, see Millgram 1997.) Perhaps these capacities for emotional judgment enable strictly moral learning in roughly the same way that chess-players’ trained sensibilities enable them to recognize the threat in a previously unencountered situation on the chessboard (Lance and Tanesini 2004). That is to say, perhaps our moral emotions play a crucial role in the exercise of a skill whereby we come to be able to articulate moral insights that we have never before attained. Perhaps competing moral considerations interact in contextually specific and complex ways much as competing chess considerations do. If so, it would make sense to rely on our emotionally-guided capacities of judgment to cope with complexities that we cannot model explicitly, but also to hope that, once having been so guided, we might in retrospect be able to articulate something about the lesson of a well-navigated situation.

A different model of strictly moral learning puts the emphasis on our after-the-fact reactions rather than on any prior, tacit emotional or judgmental guidance: the model of “experiments in living,” to use John Stuart Mill’s phrase (see Anderson 1991). Here, the basic thought is that we can try something and see if “it works.” For this to be an alternative to empirical learning about what causally conduces to what, it must be the case that we remain open as to what we mean by things “working.” In Mill’s terminology, for instance, we need to remain open as to what are the important “parts” of happiness. If we are, then perhaps we can learn by experience what some of them are – that is, what are some of the constitutive means of happiness. These paired thoughts, that our practical life is experimental and that we have no firmly fixed conception of what it is for something to “work,” come to the fore in Dewey’s pragmatist ethics (see esp. Dewey 1967 [1922]). This experimentalist conception of strictly moral learning is brought to bear on moral reasoning in Dewey’s eloquent characterizations of “practical intelligence” as involving a creative and flexible approach to figuring out “what works” in a way that is thoroughly open to rethinking our ultimate aims.

Once we recognize that moral learning is a possibility for us, we can recognize a broader range of ways of coping with moral conflicts than was canvassed in the last section. There, moral conflicts were described in a way that assumed that the set of moral considerations, among which conflicts were arising, was to be taken as fixed. If we can learn, morally, however, then we probably can and should revise the set of moral considerations that we recognize. Often, we do this by re-interpreting some moral principle that we had started with, whether by making it more specific, making it more abstract, or in some other way (cf. Richardson 2000 and 2018).

2.7 How Can We Reason, Morally, With One Another?

So far, we have mainly been discussing moral reasoning as if it were a solitary endeavor. This is, at best, a convenient simplification. At worst, it is, as Jürgen Habermas has long argued, deeply distorting of reasoning’s essentially dialogical or conversational character (e.g., Habermas 1984; cf. Laden 2012). In any case, it is clear that we often do need to reason morally with one another.

Here, we are interested in how people may actually reason with one another – not in how imagined participants in an original position or ideal speech situation may be said to reason with one another, which is a concern for moral theory, proper. There are two salient and distinct ways of thinking about people morally reasoning with one another: as members of an organized or corporate body that is capable of reaching practical decisions of its own; and as autonomous individuals working outside any such structure to figure out with each other what they ought, morally, to do.

The nature and possibility of collective reasoning within an organized collective body has recently been the subject of some discussion. Collectives can reason if they are structured as an agent. This structure might or might not be institutionalized. In line with the gloss of reasoning offered above, which presupposes being guided by an assessment of one’s reasons, it is plausible to hold that a group agent “counts as reasoning, not just rational, only if it is able to form not only beliefs in propositions – that is, object-language beliefs – but also belief about propositions” (List and Pettit 2011, 63). As List and Pettit have shown (2011, 109–113), participants in a collective agent will unavoidably have incentives to misrepresent their own preferences in conditions involving ideologically structured disagreements where the contending parties are oriented to achieving or avoiding certain outcomes – as is sometimes the case where serious moral disagreements arise. In contexts where what ultimately matters is how well the relevant group or collective ends up faring, “team reasoning” that takes advantage of orientation towards the collective flourishing of the group can help it reach a collectively optimal outcome (Sugden 1993, Bacharach 2006; see entry on collective intentionality). Where the group in question is smaller than the set of persons, however, such a collectively prudential focus is distinct from a moral focus and seems at odds with the kind of impartiality typically thought distinctive of the moral point of view. Thinking about what a “team-orientation” to the set all persons might look like might bring us back to thoughts of Kantian universalizability; but recall that here we are focused on actual reasoning, not hypothetical reasoning. With regard to actual reasoning, even if individuals can take up such an orientation towards the “team” of all persons, there is serious reason, highlighted by another strand of the Kantian tradition, for doubting that any individual can aptly surrender their moral judgment to any group’s verdict (Wolff 1998).

This does not mean that people cannot reason together, morally. It suggests, however, that such joint reasoning is best pursued as a matter of working out together, as independent moral agents, what they ought to do with regard to an issue on which they have some need to cooperate. Even if deferring to another agent’s verdict as to how one morally ought to act is off the cards, it is still possible that one may licitly take account of the moral testimony of others (for differing views, see McGrath 2009, Enoch 2014).

In the case of independent individuals reasoning morally with one another, we may expect that moral disagreement provides the occasion rather than an obstacle. To be sure, if individuals’ moral disagreement is very deep, they may not be able to get this reasoning off the ground; but as Kant’s example of Charles V and his brother each wanting Milan reminds us, intractable disagreement can arise also from disagreements that, while conceptually shallow, are circumstantially sharp. If it were true that clear-headed justification of one’s moral beliefs required seeing them as being ultimately grounded in a priori principles, as G.A. Cohen argued (Cohen 2008, chap. 6), then room for individuals to work out their moral disagreements by reasoning with one another would seem to be relatively restricted; but whether the nature of (clearheaded) moral grounding is really so restricted is seriously doubtful (Richardson 2018, §9.2). In contrast to what such a picture suggests, individuals’ moral commitments seem sufficiently open to being re-thought that people seem able to engage in principled – that is, not simply loss-minimizing – compromise (Richardson 2018, §8.5).

What about the possibility that the moral community as a whole – roughly, the community of all persons – can reason? This possibility does not raise the kind of threat to impartiality that is raised by the team reasoning of a smaller group of people; but it is hard to see it working in a way that does not run afoul of the concern about whether any person can aptly defer, in a strong sense, to the moral judgments of another agent. Even so, a residual possibility remains, which is that the moral community can reason in just one way, namely by accepting or ratifying a moral conclusion that has already become shared in a sufficiently inclusive and broad way (Richardson 2018, chap. 7).

Bibliography

  • Anderson, E. S., 1991. “John Stuart Mill and experiments in living,” Ethics, 102: 4–26.
  • Anderson, E. S. and Pildes, R. H., 2000. “Expressive theories of law: A general restatement,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 148: 1503–1575.
  • Arpaly, N. and Schroeder, T. In praise of desire, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Audi, R., 1989. Practical reasoning, London: Routledge.
  • –––. 2004. The good in the right: A theory of good and intrinsic value, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Bacharach, M., 2006. Beyond individual choice: Teams and frames in game theory, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Beauchamp, T. L., 1979. “A reply to Rachels on active and passive euthanasia,” in Medical responsibility, ed. W. L. Robinson, Clifton, N.J.: Humana Press, 182–95.
  • Brandt, R. B., 1979. A theory of the good and the right, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Bratman, M., 1999. Faces of intention: Selected essays on intention and agency, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
  • Broome, J., 2009. “The unity of reasoning?” in Spheres of reason, ed. S. Robertson, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2013. Rationality through Reasoning, Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley Blackwell.
  • Campbell, R. and Kumar, V., 2012. “Moral reasoning on the ground,” Ethics, 122: 273–312.
  • Chang, R. (ed.), 1998. Incommensurability, incomparability, and practical reason, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Clarke, S. G., and E. Simpson, 1989. Anti-theory in ethics and moral conservativism, Albany: SUNY Press.
  • Dancy, J., 1993. Moral reasons, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2004. Ethics without principles, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Dewey, J., 1967. The middle works, 1899–1924, Vol. 14, Human nature and conduct, ed. J. A. Boydston, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
  • Donagan, A., 1977. The theory of morality, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Dworkin, R., 1978. Taking rights seriously, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Engstrom, S., 2009. The form of practical knowledge: A study of the categorical imperative, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Enoch, D., 2014. “In defense of moral deference,” Journal of philosophy, 111: 229–58.
  • Fernandez, P. A., 2016. “Practical reasoning: Where the action is,” Ethics, 126: 869–900.
  • Fletcher, J., 1997. Situation ethics: The new morality, Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press.
  • Frankfurt, H. G., 1988. The importance of what we care about: Philosophical essays, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gert, B., 1998. Morality: Its nature and justification, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Gibbard, Allan, 1965. “Rule-utilitarianism: Merely an illusory alternative?,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 43: 211–220.
  • Goldman, Holly S., 1974. “David Lyons on utilitarian generalization,” Philosophical Studies, 26: 77–95.
  • Greene, J. D., 2014. “Beyond point-and-shoot morality: Why cognitive (neuro)science matters for ethics,” Ethics, 124: 695–726.
  • Habermas, J., 1984. The theory of communicative action: Vol. I, Reason and the rationalization of society, Boston: Beacon Press.
  • Haidt, J., 2001. “The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment,” Psychological Review, 108: 814–34.
  • Hare, R. M., 1981. Moral thinking: Its levels, method, and point, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Harman, G., 1986. Change in view: principles of peasoning, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
  • Held, V., 1995. Justice and care: Essential readings in feminist ethics, Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
  • Hieronymi, P., 2013. “The use of reasons in thought (and the use of earmarks in arguments),” Ethics, 124: 124–27.
  • Horty, J. F., 2012. Reasons as defaults, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2016. “Reasoning with precedents as constrained natural reasoning,” in E. Lord and B. McGuire (eds.), Weighing Reasons, Oxford: Oxford University Press: 193–212.
  • Hume, D., 2000 [1739–40]. A treatise of human nature, ed. D. F. Norton and M. J. Norton, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Hurley, S. L., 1989. Natural reasons: Personality and polity, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Jonsen, A. R., and S. Toulmin, 1988. The abuse of casuistry: A history of moral reasoning, Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Kagan, S., 1988. “The additive fallacy,” Ethics, 90: 5–31.
  • Knobe, J., 2006. “The concept of individual action: A case study in the uses of folk psychology,” Philosophical Studies, 130: 203–231.
  • Koenigs, M., 2007. “Damage to the prefrontal cortex increases utilitarian moral judgments,” Nature, 446: 908–911.
  • Kolodny, N., 2005. “Why be rational?” Mind, 114: 509–63.
  • Laden, A. S., 2012. Reasoning: A social picture, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Korsgaard, C. M., 1996. Creating the kingdom of ends, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lance, M. and Little, M., 2007. “Where the Laws Are,” in R. Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Volume 2), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • List, C. and Pettit, P., 2011. Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McDowell, John, 1998. Mind, value, and reality, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • McGrath, S., 2009. “The puzzle of moral deference,” Philosophical Perspectives, 23: 321–44.
  • McKeever, S. and Ridge, M. 2006., Principled Ethics: Generalism as a Regulative Idea, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • McNaughton, D., 1988. Moral vision: An introduction to ethics, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Mill, J. S., 1979 [1861]. Utilitarianism, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
  • Millgram, E., 1997. Practical induction, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Mikhail, J., 2011. Elements of moral cognition: Rawls’s linguistic analogy and the cognitive science of moral and legal judgment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Nell, O., 1975. Acting on principle: An essay on Kantian ethics, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Nussbaum, M. C., 1990. Love’s knowledge: Essays on philosophy and literature, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2001. Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions, Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
  • Pietroski, P. J., 1993. “Prima facie obligations, ceteris paribus laws in moral theory,” Ethics, 103: 489–515.
  • Prinz, J., 2007. The emotional construction of morals, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Rachels, J., 1975. “Active and passive euthanasia,” New England Journal of Medicine, 292: 78–80.
  • Railton, P., 1984. “Alienation, consequentialism, and the demands of morality,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13: 134–71.
  • –––, 2014. “The affective dog and its rational tale: Intuition and attunement,” Ethics, 124: 813–59.
  • Rawls, J., 1971. A theory of justice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1996. Political liberalism, New York: Columbia University Press.
  • –––, 1999. A theory of justice, revised edition, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2000. Lectures on the history of moral philosophy, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
  • Raz, J., 1990. Practical reason and norms, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Richardson, H. S., 1994. Practical reasoning about final ends, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2000. “Specifying, balancing, and interpreting bioethical principles,” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 25: 285–307.
  • –––, 2002. Democratic autonomy: Public reasoning about the ends of policy, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2004. “Thinking about conflicts of desires,” in Practical conflicts: New philosophical essays, eds. P. Baumann and M. Betzler, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 96–117.
  • –––, 2018. Articulating the moral community: Toward a constructive ethical pragmatism, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Ross, W. D., 1988. The right and the good, Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Sandel, M., 1998. Liberalism and the limits of justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Sartre, J. P., 1975. “Existentialism is a Humanism,” in Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre, ed. W. Kaufmann, New York: Meridian-New American, 345–69.
  • Scheffler, Samuel, 1992. Human morality, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Schmidtz, D., 1995. Rational choice and moral agency, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Schneewind, J.B., 1977. Sidgwick’s ethics and Victorian moral philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Schroeder, M., 2011. “Holism, weight, and undercutting.” Noûs, 45: 328–44.
  • Schwitzgebel, E. and Cushman, F., 2012. “Expertise in moral reasoning? Order effects on moral judgment in professional philosophers and non-philosophers,” Mind and Language, 27: 135–53.
  • Sidgwick, H., 1981. The methods of ethics, reprinted, 7th edition, Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W., 1988. Moral dilemmas, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Smith, M., 1994. The moral problem, Oxford: Blackwell.
  • –––, 2013. “A constitutivist theory of reasons: Its promise and parts,” Law, Ethics and Philosophy, 1: 9–30.
  • Sneddon, A., 2007. “A social model of moral dumbfounding: Implications for studying moral reasoning and moral judgment,” Philosophical Psychology, 20: 731–48.
  • Sugden, R., 1993. “Thinking as a team: Towards an explanation of nonselfish behavior,” Social Philosophy and Policy, 10: 69–89.
  • Sunstein, C. R., 1996. Legal reasoning and political conflict, New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Tiberius, V., 2000. “Humean heroism: Value commitments and the source of normativity,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 81: 426–446.
  • Vogler, C., 1998. “Sex and talk,” Critical Inquiry, 24: 328–65.
  • Wellman, H. and Miller, J., 2008. “Including deontic reasoning as fundamental to theory of mind,” Human Development, 51: 105–35
  • Williams, B., 1981. Moral luck: Philosophical papers 1973–1980, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Wolff, R. P., 1998. In defense of anarchism, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  • Young, L. and Saxe, R., 2008. “The neural basis of belief encoding and integration in moral judgment,” NeuroImage, 40: 1912–20.

 

 

 

 

                                                      W

 

Here is a Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on Hume’s Moral Philosophy.

 

 

 

Article 22 (A22 after this): “

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Hume’s Moral Philosophy

First published Fri Oct 29, 2004; substantive revision Mon Aug 20, 2018

Hume’s position in ethics, which is based on his empiricist theory of the mind, is best known for asserting four theses: (1) Reason alone cannot be a motive to the will, but rather is the “slave of the passions” (see Section 3)”

My response: Reason is not the only motive to will, but it is the primary one.

A22: “(2) Moral distinctions are not derived from reason (see Section 4). (3) Moral distinctions are derived from the moral sentiments: feelings of approval (esteem, praise) and disapproval (blame) felt by spectators who contemplate a character trait or action (see Section 7). (4) While some virtues and vices are natural (see Section 13), others, including justice, are artificial (see Section 9). There is heated debate about what Hume intends by each of these theses and how he argues for them. He articulates and defends them within the broader context of his metaethics and his ethic of virtue and vice.”

My response: There may be both natural and artificial virtues and vices, for I had not much considered this.

A22: “Hume’s main ethical writings are Book 3 of his Treatise of Human Nature, “Of Morals” (which builds on Book 2, “Of the Passions”), his Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, and some of his Essays. In part the moral Enquiry simply recasts central ideas from the moral part of the Treatise in a more accessible style; but there are important differences. The ethical positions and arguments of the Treatise are set out below, noting where the moral Enquiry agrees; differences between the Enquiry and the Treatise are discussed afterwards.


1. Issues from Hume’s Predecessors

Hume inherits from his predecessors several controversies about ethics and political philosophy.

One is a question of moral epistemology: how do human beings become aware of, or acquire knowledge or belief about, moral good and evil, right and wrong, duty and obligation? Ethical theorists and theologians of the day held, variously, that moral good and evil are discovered: (a) by reason in some of its uses (Hobbes, Locke, Clarke), (b) by divine revelation (Filmer), (c) by conscience or reflection on one’s (other) impulses (Butler), or (d) by a moral sense: an emotional responsiveness manifesting itself in approval or disapproval (Shaftesbury, Hutcheson). Hume sides with the moral sense theorists: we gain awareness of moral good and evil by experiencing the pleasure of approval and the uneasiness of disapproval when we contemplate a character trait or action from an imaginatively sensitive and unbiased point of view. Hume maintains against the rationalists that, although reason is needed to discover the facts of any concrete situation and the general social impact of a trait of character or a practice over time, reason alone is insufficient to yield a judgment that something is virtuous or vicious. In the last analysis, the facts as known must trigger a response by sentiment or “taste.””

My response: As a moderate I believe we can discover what is moral goodness and moral evil  by reason, divine revelation, conscience (the internal voice of God) and moral sense. Hume the sentimentalist concludes moral judgement are felt sentiment or personal taste in in reaction to what one has perceived or experienced.

A22: “A related but more metaphysical controversy would be stated thus today: what is the source or foundation of moral norms? In Hume’s day this is the question what is the ground of moral obligation (as distinct from what is the faculty for acquiring moral knowledge or belief). Moral rationalists of the period such as Clarke (and in some moods, Hobbes and Locke) argue that moral standards or principles are requirements of reason — that is, that the very rationality of right actions is the ground of our obligation to perform them. Divine voluntarists of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries such as Samuel Pufendorf claim that moral obligation or requirement, if not every sort of moral standard, is the product of God’s will. The moral sense theorists (Shaftesbury and Hutcheson) and Butler see all requirements to pursue goodness and avoid evil as consequent upon human nature, which is so structured that a particular feature of our consciousness (whether moral sense or conscience) evaluates the rest. Hume sides with the moral sense theorists on this question: it is because we are the kinds of creatures we are, with the dispositions we have for pain and pleasure, the kinds of familial and friendly interdependence that make up our life together, and our approvals and disapprovals of these, that we are bound by moral requirements at all.

Closely connected with the issue of the foundations of moral norms is the question whether moral requirements are natural or conventional. Hobbes and Mandeville see them as conventional, and Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Locke, and others see them as natural. Hume mocks Mandeville’s contention that the very concepts of vice and virtue are foisted on us by scheming politicians trying to manage us more easily. If there were nothing in our experience and no sentiments in our minds to produce the concept of virtue, Hume says, no lavish praise of heroes could generate it. So to a degree moral requirements have a natural origin. Nonetheless,Hume thinks natural impulses of humanity and dispositions to approve cannot entirely account for our virtue of justice; a correct analysis of that virtue reveals that mankind, an “inventive species,” has cooperatively constructed rules of property and promise. Thus he takes an intermediate position: some virtues are natural, and some are the products of convention.”

My response: The foundations of moral norms are supernatural, natural, and then social.

A22: “Linked with these meta-ethical controversies is the dilemma of understanding the ethical life either as the “ancients” do, in terms of virtues and vices of character, or as the “moderns” do, primarily in terms of principles of duty or natural law. While even so law-oriented a thinker as Hobbes has a good deal to say about virtue, the ethical writers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries predominantly favor a rule- or law-governed understanding of morals, giving priority to laws of nature or principles of duty. The chief exception here is the moral sense school, which advocates an analysis of the moral life more like that of the Greek and Hellenistic thinkers, in terms of settled traits of character — although they too find a place for principles in their ethics. Hume explicitly favors an ethic of character along “ancient” lines. Yet he insists on a role for rules of duty within the domain of what he calls the artificial virtues.

Hume’s predecessors famously took opposing positions on whether human nature was essentially selfish or benevolent, some arguing that man was so dominated by self-interested motives that for moral requirements to govern us at all they must serve our interests in some way, and others arguing that uncorrupted human beings naturally care about the weal and woe of others and here morality gets its hold.”

My response: Observe that, those that condemn humans and their basic natures as evil, equate being evil with being selfish, and those who insist human nature is basically good, present that human goodness of nature naturally, or achieved by willing upbringing, is benevolently and unselfishly defined.

I describe human nature as basically evil and that is the same as being unselfish and selfless. We learn to be self-interested and self-concerned and that is virtue.

Humans require some rewards to behave, things like social approval or faith in the afterlife.

The altruists describe human nature as neutral or benevolent, that society corrupts the natural inclination to care for others.

A22: “Hume roundly criticizes Hobbes for his insistence on psychological egoism or something close to it, and for his dismal, violent picture of a state of nature. Yet Hume resists the view of Hutcheson that all moral principles can be reduced to our benevolence, in part because he doubts that benevolence can sufficiently overcome our perfectly normal acquisitiveness. According to Hume’s observation, we are both selfish and humane. We possess greed, and also “limited generosity” — dispositions to kindness and liberality which are more powerfully directed toward kin and friends and less aroused by strangers. While for Hume the condition of humankind in the absence of organized society is not a war of all against all, neither is it the law-governed and highly cooperative domain imagined by Locke. It is a hypothetical condition in which we would care for our friends and cooperate with them, but in which self-interest and preference for friends over strangers would make any wider cooperation impossible. Hume’s empirically-based thesis that we are fundamentally loving, parochial, and also selfish creatures underlies his political philosophy.

In the realm of politics, Hume again takes up an intermediate position. He objects both to the doctrine that a subject must passively obey his government no matter how tyrannical it is and to the Lockean thesis that citizens have a natural right to revolution whenever their rulers violate their contractual commitments to the people. He famously criticizes the notion that all political duties arise from an implicit contract that binds later generations who were not party to the original explicit agreement. Hume maintains that the duty to obey one’s government has an independent origin that parallels that of promissory obligation: both are invented to enable people to live together successfully. On his view, human beings can create a society without government, ordered by conventional rules of ownership, transfer of property by consent, and promise-keeping. We superimpose government on such a pre-civil society when it grows large and prosperous; only then do we need to use political power to enforce these rules of justice in order to preserve social cooperation. So the duty of allegiance to government, far from depending on the duty to fulfill promises, provides needed assurance that promises of all sorts will be kept. The duty to submit to our rulers comes into being because reliable submission is necessary to preserve order. Particular governments are legitimate because of their usefulness in preserving society, not because those who wield power were chosen by God or received promises of obedience from the people. In a long-established civil society, whatever ruler or type of government happens to be in place and successfully maintaining order and justice is legitimate, and is owed allegiance. However, there is some legitimate recourse for victims of tyranny: the people may rightly overthrow any government that is so oppressive as not to provide the benefits (peace and security from injustice) for which governments are formed. In his political essays Hume certainly advocates the sort of constitution that protects the people’s liberties, but he justifies it not based on individual natural rights or contractual obligations but based on the greater long-range good of society.

2. The Passions and the Will

According to Hume’s theory of the mind, the passions (what we today would call emotions, feelings, and desires) are impressions rather than ideas (original, vivid and lively perceptions that are not copied from other perceptions). The direct passions, which include desire, aversion, hope, fear, grief, and joy, are those that “arise immediately from good or evil, from pain or pleasure” that we experience or think about in prospect (T 2.1.1.4, T 2.3.9.2); however he also groups with them some instincts of unknown origin, such as the bodily appetites and the desires that good come to those we love and harm to those we hate, which do not proceed from pain and pleasure but produce them (T 2.3.9.7). The indirect passions, primarily pride, humility (shame), love and hatred, are generated in a more complex way, but still one involving either the thought or experience of pain or pleasure. Intentional actions are caused by the direct passions (including the instincts). Of the indirect passions Hume says that pride, humility, love and hatred do not directly cause action; it is not clear whether he thinks this true of all the indirect passions.

Hume is traditionally regarded as a compatibilist about freedom and determinism, because in his discussion in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding he argues that if we understand the doctrines of liberty and necessity properly, all mankind consistently believe both that human actions are the products of causal necessity and that they are free. In the Treatise, however, he explicitly repudiates the doctrine of liberty as “absurd... in one sense, and unintelligible in any other” (T 2.3.2.1). The two treatments, however, surprisingly enough, are entirely consistent. Hume construes causal necessity to mean the same as causal connection (or rather, intelligible causal connection), as he himself analyzes this notion in his own theory of causation: either the “constant union and conjunction of like objects,” or that together with “the inference of the mind from the one to the other” (ibid.). In both works he argues that just as we discover necessity (in this sense) to hold between the movements of material bodies, we discover just as much necessity to hold between human motives, character traits, and circumstances of action, on the one hand, and human behavior on the other. He says in the Treatise that the liberty of indifference is the negation of necessity in this sense; this is the notion of liberty that he there labels absurd, and identifies with chance or randomness (which can be no real power in nature) both in the Treatise and the first (epistemological) Enquiry. Human actions are not free in this sense. However, Hume allows in the Treatise that they are sometimes free in the sense of ‘liberty’ which is opposed to violence or constraint. This is the sense on which Hume focuses in EcHU: “a power of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the will;” which everyone has “who is not a prisoner and in chains” (EcHU 8.1.23, Hume’s emphasis). It is this that is entirely compatible with necessity in Hume’s sense. So the positions in the two works are the same, although the polemical emphasis is so different — iconoclastic toward the libertarian view in the Treatise, and conciliatory toward “all mankind” in the first Enquiry.

Hume argues, as well, that the causal necessity of human actions is not only compatible with moral responsibility but requisite to it. To hold an agent morally responsible for a bad action, it is not enough that the action be morally reprehensible; we must impute the badness of the fleeting act to the enduring agent. Not all harmful or forbidden actions incur blame for the agent; those done by accident, for example, do not. It is only when, and because, the action’s cause is some enduring passion or trait of character in the agent that she is to blame for it.

3. The Influencing Motives of the Will

According to Hume, intentional actions are the immediate product of passions, in particular the direct passions, including the instincts. He does not appear to allow that any other sort of mental state could, on its own, give rise to an intentional action except by producing a passion, though he does not argue for this. The motivating passions, in their turn, are produced in the mind by specific causes, as we see early in the Treatise where he first explains the distinction between impressions of sensation and impressions of reflection:

An impression first strikes upon the senses, and makes us perceive heat or cold, thirst or hunger, pleasure or pain, of some kind or other. Of this impression there is a copy taken by the mind, which remains after the impression ceases; and this we call an idea. This idea of pleasure or pain, when it returns upon the soul, produces the new impressions of desire and aversion, hope and fear, which may properly be called impressions of reflection, because derived from it. (T 1.1.2.2)

Thus ideas of pleasure or pain are the causes of these motivating passions. Not just any ideas of pleasure or pain give rise to motivating passions, however, but only ideas of those pleasures or pains we believe exist or will exist (T 1.3.10.3). More generally, the motivating passions of desire and aversion, hope and fear, joy and grief, and a few others are impressions produced by the occurrence in the mind either of a feeling of pleasure or pain, whether physical or psychological, or of a believed idea of pleasure or pain to come (T 2.1.1.4, T 2.3.9.2). These passions, together with the instincts (hunger, lust, and so on), are all the motivating passions that Hume discusses.

The will, Hume claims, is an immediate effect of pain or pleasure (T 2.3.1.2) and “exerts itself” when either pleasure or the absence of pain can be attained by any action of the mind or body (T 2.3.9.7). The will, however, is merely that impression we feel when we knowingly give rise to an action (T 2.3.1.2); so while Hume is not explicit (and perhaps not consistent) on this matter, he seems not to regard the will as itself a (separate) cause of action. The causes of action he describes are those he has already identified: the instincts and the other direct passions.

Hume famously sets himself in opposition to most moral philosophers, ancient and modern, who talk of the combat of passion and reason, and who urge human beings to regulate their actions by reason and to grant it dominion over their contrary passions. He claims to prove that “reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will,” and that reason alone “can never oppose passion in the direction of the will” (T 413). His view is not, of course, that reason plays no role in the generation of action; he grants that reason provides information, in particular about means to our ends, which makes a difference to the direction of the will. His thesis is that reason alone cannot move us to action; the impulse to act itself must come from passion. The doctrine that reason alone is merely the “slave of the passions,” i.e., that reason pursues knowledge of abstract and causal relations solely in order to achieve passions’ goals and provides no impulse of its own, is defended in the Treatise, but not in the second Enquiry, although in the latter he briefly asserts the doctrine without argument. Hume gives three arguments in the Treatise for the motivational “inertia” of reason alone.

The first is a largely empirical argument based on the two rational functions of the understanding. The understanding discovers the abstract relations of ideas by demonstration (a process of comparing ideas and finding congruencies and incongruencies); and it also discovers the causal (and other probabilistic) relations of objects that are revealed in experience. Demonstrative reasoning is never the cause of any action by itself: it deals in ideas rather than realities, and we only find it useful in action when we have some purpose in view and intend to use its discoveries to inform our inferences about (and so enable us to manipulate) causes and effects. Probable or cause-and-effect reasoning does play a role in deciding what to do, but we see that it only functions as an auxiliary, and not on its own. When we anticipate pain or pleasure from some source, we feel aversion or propensity to that object and “are carry’d to avoid or embrace what will give us” the pain or pleasure (T 2.3.3.3). Our aversion or propensity makes us seek the causes of the expected source of pain or pleasure, and we use causal reasoning to discover what they are. Once we do, our impulse naturally extends itself to those causes, and we act to avoid or embrace them. Plainly the impulse to act does not arise from the reasoning but is only directed by it. “’Tis from the prospect of pain or pleasure that the aversion or propensity arises...” (ibid.). Probable reasoning is merely the discovering of causal connections, and knowledge that A causes B never concerns us if we are indifferent to A and to B. Thus, neither demonstrative nor probable reasoning alone causes action.

The second argument is a corollary of the first. It takes as a premise the conclusion just reached, that reason alone cannot produce an impulse to act. Given that, can reason prevent action or resist passion in controlling the will? To stop a volition or retard the impulse of an existing passion would require a contrary impulse. If reason alone could give rise to such a contrary impulse, it would have an original influence on the will (a capacity to cause intentional action, when unopposed); which, according to the previous argument, it lacks. Therefore reason alone cannot resist any impulse to act. Therefore, what offers resistance to our passions cannot be reason of itself. Hume later proposes that when we restrain imprudent or immoral impulses, the contrary impulse comes also from passion, but often from a passion so “calm” that we confuse it with reason.

The third or Representation argument is different in kind. Hume offers it initially only to show that a passion cannot be opposed by or be contradictory to “truth and reason”; later (T 3.1.1.9), he repeats and expands it to argue that volitions and actions as well cannot be so. One might suppose he means to give another argument to show that reason alone cannot provide a force to resist passion. Yet the Representation Argument is not empirical, and does not talk of forces or impulses. Passions (and volitions and actions), Hume says, do not refer to other entities; they are “original existence[s],” (T 2.3.3.5), “original facts and realities” (T3.1.1.9), not mental representations of other things. Since Hume here understands representation in terms of copying, he says a passion has no “representative quality, which renders it a copy of any other existence or modification” (T 2.3.3.5). Contradiction to truth and reason, however, consists in “the disagreement of ideas, consider’d as copies, with those objects, which they represent” (ibid.). Therefore, a passion (or volition or action), not having this feature, cannot be opposed by truth and reason. The argument allegedly proves two points: first, that actions cannot be reasonable or unreasonable; second, that “reason cannot immediately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or approving of it” (T3.1.1.10). The point here is not merely the earlier, empirical observation that the rational activity of the understanding does not generate an impulse in the absence of an expectation of pain or pleasure. The main point is that, because passions, volitions, and actions have no content suitable for assessment by reason, reason cannot assess prospective motives or actions as rational or irrational; and therefore reason cannot, by so assessing them, create or obstruct them. By contrast, reason can assess a potential opinion as rational or irrational; and by endorsing the opinion, reason will (that is, we will) adopt it, while by contradicting the opinion, reason will destroy our credence in it. The Representation Argument, then, makes a point a priori about the relevance of the functions of the understanding to the generation of actions. Interpreters disagree about exactly how to parse this argument, whether it is sound, and its importance to Hume’s project.

Hume allows that, speaking imprecisely, we often say a passion is unreasonable because it arises in response to a mistaken judgment or opinion, either that something (a source of pleasure or uneasiness) exists, or that it may be obtained or avoided by a certain means. In just these two cases a passion may be called unreasonable, but strictly speaking even here it is not the passion but the judgment that is so. Once we correct the mistaken judgment, “our passions yield to our reason without any opposition,” so there is still no combat of passion and reason (T 2.3.3.7). And there is no other instance of passion contrary to reason. Hume famously declaims, “’Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger. ‘Tis not contrary to reason for me to chuse my total ruin, to prevent the least uneasiness of an Indian or person wholly unknown to me. ‘Tis as little contrary to reason to prefer even my own acknowledg’d lesser good to my greater, and have a more ardent affection for the former than for the latter.” (2.3.3.6)

Interpreters disagree as to whether Hume is an instrumentalist or a skeptic about practical reason. Either way, Hume denies that reason can evaluate the ends people set themselves; only passions can select ends, and reason cannot evaluate passions.”

My response: I disagree that only passions select ends. Humans are hopelessly complicated.

A 22:  Instrumentalists understand the claim that reason is the slave of the passions to allow that reason not only discovers the causally efficacious means to our ends (a task of theoretical causal reasoning) but also requires us to take them. If Hume regards the failure to take the known means to one’s end as contrary to reason, then on Hume’s view reason has a genuinely practical aspect: it can classify some actions as unreasonable. Skeptical interpreters read Hume, instead, as denying that reason imposes any requirements on action, even the requirement to take the known, available means to one’s end. They point to the list of extreme actions that are not contrary to reason (such as preferring one’s own lesser good to one’s greater), and to the Representation Argument, which denies that any passions, volitions, or actions are of such a nature as to be contrary to reason. Hume never says explicitly that failing to take the known means to one’s end is either contrary to reason or not contrary to reason (it is not one of the extreme cases in his list). The classificatory point in the Representation Argument favors the reading of Hume as a skeptic about practical reason; but that argument is absent from the moral Enquiry.”

My response: Hume may in fact be silent about being a practical reasoning skeptic, but his being such a skeptic seems intuitively fitting.

A22: “4. Ethical Anti-rationalism

Hume claims that moral distinctions are not derived from reason but rather from sentiment. His rejection of ethical rationalism is at least two-fold. Moral rationalists tend to say, first, that moral properties are discovered by reason, and also that what is morally good is in accord with reason (even that goodness consists in reasonableness) and what is morally evil is unreasonable.”

My response: What is morally good is reasonable, and what is wicked is unreasonable. Reason can discover moral properties, and what is morally good must be reasonable, sane, moderate, and prudent.

A22: “Hume rejects both theses. Some of his arguments are directed to one and some to the other thesis, and in places it is unclear which he means to attack.

In the Treatise he argues against the epistemic thesis (that we discover good and evil by reasoning) by showing that neither demonstrative nor probable/causal reasoning has vice and virtue as its proper objects. Demonstrative reasoning discovers relations of ideas, and vice and virtue are not identical with any of the four philosophical relations (resemblance, contrariety, degrees in quality, or proportions in quantity and number) whose presence can be demonstrated. Nor could they be identical with any other abstract relation; for such relations can also obtain between items such as trees that are incapable of moral good or evil. Furthermore, were moral vice and virtue discerned by demonstrative reasoning, such reasoning would reveal their inherent power to produce motives in all who discern them; but no causal connections can be discovered a priori. Causal reasoning, by contrast, does infer matters of fact pertaining to actions, in particular their causes and effects; but the vice of an action (its wickedness) is not found in its causes or effects, but is only apparent when we consult the sentiments of the observer. Therefore moral good and evil are not discovered by reason alone.”

My response: Hume’s skepticism about moral reasoning and that we can choose based on our conclusion of a practical, moral syllogism, is not without sting, but I can imagine that Ayn Rand would have dismissed him out of hand.

A22: “Hume also attempts in the Treatise to establish the other anti-rationalist thesis, that virtue is not the same as reasonableness and vice is not contrary to reason. He gives two arguments for this. The first, very short, argument he claims follows directly from the Representation Argument, whose conclusion was that passions, volitions, and actions can be neither reasonable nor unreasonable. Actions, he observes, can be laudable or blamable. Since actions cannot be reasonable or against reason, it follows that “[l]audable and blameable are not the same with reasonable or unreasonable” (T 458). The properties are not identical.”

My response: As an ontological and moral moderate, I counter-argue against Hume that laudable is close to being reasonable, and blamable is close to be unreasonable, but, as a minority moral stance, he has a point that our innate conscience or moral sense, if we are truth-oriented, realistic, and truth-bound, can immediately and precisely detect which action is laudable and or blamable, so moral sentiment plays a significant if minor moral choice role.

A22: “The second and more famous argument makes use of the conclusion defended earlier that reason alone cannot move us to act. As we have seen, reason alone “can never immediately prevent or produce any action by contradicting or approving of it” (T 458). Morality — this argument goes on — influences our passions and actions: we are often impelled to or deterred from action by our opinions of obligation or injustice. Therefore morals cannot be derived from reason alone. This argument is first introduced as showing it impossible “from reason alone... to distinguish betwixt moral good and evil” (T 457) — that is, it is billed as establishing the epistemic thesis. But Hume also says that, like the little direct argument above, it proves that “actions do not derive their merit from a conformity to reason, nor their blame from a contrariety to it” (T458): it is not the reasonableness of an action that makes it good, or its unreasonableness that makes it evil.”

My response: Hume has a point in denying what is blamable or praiseworthy is not the same as being unreasonable or reasonable.

A22: “This argument about motives concludes that moral judgments or evaluations are not the products of reason alone. From this many draw the sweeping conclusion that for Hume moral evaluations are not beliefs or opinions of any kind, but lack all cognitive content. That is, they take the argument to show that Hume holds a non-propositional view of moral evaluations — and indeed, given his sentimentalism, that he is an emotivist: one who holds that moral judgments are meaningless ventings of emotion that can be neither true nor false. Such a reading should be met with caution, however. For Hume, to say that something is not a product of reason alone is not equivalent to saying it is not a truth-evaluable judgment or belief. Hume does not consider all our (propositional) beliefs and opinions to be products of reason; some arise directly from sense perception, for example, and some from sympathy.”

My response: This is a cautionary not for the reader—that Hume to say that something being not a product of reason is equivalent to saying it is not a truth-evaluable judgment or belief, because some propositional beliefs or opinion arise directly from sense perception or sympathy, Hume decided and wrote.

Hume likely is not a pure noncognitivist about moral judgements or evaluations lacking any rational input, if only as modest opinions or beliefs, and with his leaning towards a non-propositional view of moral evaluations, his sentimentalism creeps towards the boundary tipping over into skeptical, subjective, relativistic emotivism.

He did call reason the slave of the passions. And it is for nonindividuating groupists, far too often, but the reverse is desirable, not that the passions are the slave of the agent’s moral reasoning, but then feelings are felt and heeded by every self, but guided by the firm, temperate, sober hand of the logical superego, running the personal moral show.

The writer of this article sees Hume as some kind of moral moderate, that not all moral judgments are meaningless venting of emotions which can be neither true or false, but Hume leads that direction hard. Our propositional beliefs do rise from our sense perception (moral sense) and sympathy, but from antipathy towards ourselves and others, based on social clique ranking or not, the evil side of altruism enforced in the community.

On one hand I am overwhelmed by the expertise of the author of this professional ethical article, and do not comprehend all that is written; on the other hand, my rich, deep, truth-bounded Mavellonialist moral code grounds me in my own metaethical view of the landscape of moral theories out there. It occurs to me that Humean sentimentalism easily drifts over into postmodernist moral nihilism. In fact without moral realism moral theory being the norm for a people that there is no or not much of a is-ought gap at work epistemologically, ontologically or normatively, people, basically evil, basically insane, and basically addicted to and seeking suffering, without a realist, egoist moral code and a benevolent deity in their lives, they are in bondage to the Dark Couple and evil will continue to reign supreme on earth, and in most human hearts.

 A22: “Also, perhaps there are (propositional) beliefs we acquire via probable reasoning but not by such reasoning alone. One possible example is the belief that some object is a cause of pleasure, a belief that depends upon prior impressions as well as probable reasoning.”

My response: Here is where the author reveals that reasoning and a sensed impression contribute to the agent’s belief and choice about some object, fact, or choice. Likely we think and feel in the moral choices we make, sometimes more one than the other but both at the same time; we are complex creatures.

A22: “Another concern about the famous argument about motives is how it could be sound. In order for it to yield its conclusion, it seems that its premise that morality (or a moral judgment) influences the will must be construed to say that moral evaluations alone move us to action, without the help of some (further) passion. This is a controversial claim and not one for which Hume offers any support. The premise that reason alone cannot influence action is also difficult to interpret. It would seem, given his prior arguments for this claim (e.g. that the mere discovery of a causal relation does not produce an impulse to act), that Hume means by it not only that the faculty of reason or the activity of reasoning alone cannot move us, but also that the conclusions of such activity alone (such as recognition of a relation of ideas or belief in a causal connection) cannot produce a motive. Yet it is hard to see how Hume, given his theory of causation, can argue that no mental item of a certain type (such as a causal belief) can possibly cause motivating passion or action. Such a claim could not be supported a priori. And in Treatise 1.3.10, “Of the influence of belief,” he seems to assert very plainly that some causal beliefs do cause motivating passions, specifically beliefs about pleasure and pain in prospect. It is possible that Hume only means to say, in the premise that reason alone cannot influence action, that reasoning processes cannot generate actions as their logical conclusions; but that would introduce an equivocation, since he surely does not mean to say, in the other premise, that moral evaluations generate actions as their logical conclusions. The transition from premises to conclusion also seems to rely on a principle of transitivity (If A alone cannot produce X and B produces X, then A alone cannot produce B), which is doubtful but receives no defense.

Commentators have proposed various interpretations to avoid these difficulties. One approach is to construe ‘reason’ as the name of a process or activity, the comparing of ideas (reasoning), and to construe ‘morals’ as Hume uses it in this argument to mean the activity of moral discrimination (making a moral distinction). If we understand the terms this way, the argument can be read not as showing that the faculty of reason (or the beliefs it generates) cannot cause us to make moral judgments, but rather as showing that the reasoning process (comparing ideas) is distinct from the process of moral discrimination. This interpretation does not rely on an assumption about the transitivity of causation and is consistent with Hume’s theory of causation.”

My response: Here is where my lack of professional training as an analytic philosopher thwarts my comprehension of what the writer wrote just about the transivity of causation; he feels that he cannot allow equivocation to undermine Hume’s moral theory that reasoning is involved in moral decision-making merely as the process of comparing ideas, but that it is the passions of approval-pleasure or disapproval-pain concerning moral choices that push the will of the agent to choose. It is murky, I believe, for reasoning is giving us a logical train to explore about moral ideas, but it is also causal in moral choosing, and our sentiments or moral sense might well help us connect moral premises as well as inform us consciously as to what option to choose.

These intertwined and perhaps not fully, intellectually separable-from-each-other means of laying out moral arguments for ourselves, is both rational and sentimental, and the moral thinker who is cruder and less developed will only sense his options, whereas the individuated moralist likely will both sense and logically conclude or determine which option to select.

A22” 5. Is and ought

Hume famously closes the section of the Treatise that argues against moral rationalism by observing that other systems of moral philosophy, proceeding in the ordinary way of reasoning, at some point make an unremarked transition from premises whose parts are linked only by “is” to conclusions whose parts are linked by “ought” (expressing a new relation) — a deduction that seems to Hume “altogether inconceivable” (T3.1.1.27). Attention to this transition would “subvert all the vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceiv’d by reason” (ibid.).

Few passages in Hume’s work have generated more interpretive controversy.

According to the dominant twentieth-century interpretation, Hume says here that no ought-judgment may be correctly inferred from a set of premises expressed only in terms of ‘is,’ and the vulgar systems of morality commit this logical fallacy. This is usually thought to mean something much more general: that no ethical or indeed evaluative conclusion whatsoever may be validly inferred from any set of purely factual premises. A number of present-day philosophers, including R. M. Hare, endorse this putative thesis of logic, calling it “Hume’s Law.” (As Francis Snare observes, on this reading Hume must simply assume that no purely factual propositions are themselves evaluative, as he does not argue for this.) Some interpreters think Hume commits himself here to a non-propositional or noncognitivist view of moral judgment — the view that moral judgments do not state facts and are not truth-evaluable. (If Hume has already used the famous argument about the motivational influence of morals to establish noncognitivism, then the is/ought paragraph may merely draw out a trivial consequence of it. If moral evaluations are merely expressions of feeling without propositional content, then of course they cannot be inferred from any propositional premises.) Some see the paragraph as denying ethical realism, excluding values from the domain of facts.”

My response: With his is-ought gap proposal, if Hume does not commit himself to the view that moral judgements do not state facts and are not truth-evaluable, that his view of moral judgment is non-propositional and non-cognitivist, he sure fools me.

Hume the skeptic and moral anti-realist, sure seems to convey the opinion that moral evaluations are subjective, mere expressions of feelings, without propositional content. They cannot be inferred from propositional premises, and ethical realism is to be denied, and values are divorced irrevocably from the domain of facts.

Either Hume allows sometimes that what is is the basis for what ought to be, or he is a straight up anti-realist.

A22: “Other interpreters — the more cognitivist ones — see the paragraph about ‘is’ and ‘ought’ as doing none of the above. Some read it as simply providing further support for Hume’s extensive argument that moral properties are not discernible by demonstrative reason, leaving open whether ethical evaluations may be conclusions of cogent probable arguments. Others interpret it as making a point about the original discovery of virtue and vice, which must involve the use of sentiment. On this view, one cannot make the initial discovery of moral properties by inference from nonmoral premises using reason alone; rather, one requires some input from sentiment. It is not simply by reasoning from the abstract and causal relations one has discovered that one comes to have the ideas of virtue and vice; one must respond to such information with feelings of approval and disapproval. Note that on this reading it is compatible with the is/ought paragraph that once a person has the moral concepts as the result of prior experience of the moral sentiments, he or she may reach some particular moral conclusions by inference from causal, factual premises (stated in terms of ‘is’) about the effects of character traits on the sentiments of observers. They point out that Hume himself makes such inferences frequently in his writings.”

My response: Some cognitivists take a middle way, that Hume with is-ought is only denying that moral properties are discernible by demonstrative reasoning, that cogent probable arguments are achievable, sensible and applicable. When the agent’s prior experience of approving or disapproving of a similar experience is reintroduce in the practical syllogism being crafted, the agent can muddle through to a right conclusion.

A22: “6. The Nature of Moral Judgment

On Hume’s view, what is a moral evaluation? Four main interpretations have significant textual support. First, as we have seen, the nonpropositional view says that for Hume a moral evaluation does not express any proposition or state any fact; either it gives vent to a feeling, or it is itself a feeling (Flew, Blackburn, Snare, Bricke). (A more refined form of this interpretation allows that moral evaluations have some propositional content, but claims that for Hume their essential feature, as evaluations, is non-propositional.) The subjective description view, by contrast, says that for Hume moral evaluations describe the feelings of the spectator, or the feelings a spectator would have were she to contemplate the trait or action from the common point of view. Often grouped with the latter view is the third, dispositional interpretation, which understands moral evaluations as factual judgments to the effect that the evaluated trait or action is so constituted as to cause feelings of approval or disapproval in a (suitably characterized) spectator (Mackie, in one of his proposals). On the dispositional view, in saying some trait is good we attribute to the trait the dispositional property of being such as to elicit approval. A fourth interpretation distinguishes two psychological states that might be called a moral evaluation: an occurrent feeling of approval or disapproval (which is not truth-apt), and a moral belief or judgment that is propositional. Versions of this fourth interpretation differ in what they take to be the content of that latter mental state. One version says that the moral judgments, as distinct from the moral feelings, are factual judgments about the moral sentiments (Capaldi). A distinct version, the moral sensing view, treats the moral beliefs as ideas copied from the impressions of approval or disapproval that represent a trait of character or an action as having whatever quality it is that one experiences in feeling the moral sentiment (Cohon). This last view emphasizes Hume’s claim that moral good and evil are like heat, cold, and colors as understood in “modern philosophy,” which are experienced directly by sensation, but about which we form beliefs.”

My response: The introduced, four main interpretation of Hume’s view of what is a moral evaluation is outside the scope of my interest in this blog entry, but would be prospective to study and ponder.

A22: “7. Sympathy, and the Nature and Origin of the Moral Sentiments

Our moral evaluations of persons and their character traits, on Hume’s positive view, arise from our sentiments. The virtues and vices are those traits the disinterested contemplation of which produces approval and disapproval, respectively, in whoever contemplates the trait, whether the trait’s possessor or another. These moral sentiments are emotions (in the present-day sense of that term) with a unique phenomenological quality, and also with a special set of causes. They are caused by contemplating the person or action to be evaluated without regard to our self-interest, and from a common or general perspective that compensates for certain likely distortions in the observer’s sympathies, as explained in Section 8. Approval (approbation) is a pleasure, and disapproval (disapprobation) a pain or uneasiness. The moral sentiments are typically calm rather than violent, although they can be intensified by our awareness of the moral responses of others. They are types of pleasure and uneasiness that are associated with the passions of pride and humility, love and hatred: when we feel moral approval of another we tend to love or esteem her, and when we approve a trait of our own we are proud of it. Some interpreters analyze the moral sentiments as themselves forms of these four passions; others argue that Hume’s moral sentiments tend to cause the latter passions. We distinguish which traits are virtuous and which are vicious by means of our feelings of approval and disapproval toward the traits; our approval of actions is derived from approval of the traits we suppose to have given rise to them. We can determine, by observing the various sorts of traits toward which we feel approval, that every such trait — every virtue — has at least one of the following four characteristics: it is either immediately agreeable to the person who has it or to others, or it is useful (advantageous over the longer term) to its possessor or to others. Vices prove to have the parallel features: they are either immediately disagreeable or disadvantageous either to the person who has them or to others. These are not definitions of ‘virtue’ and ‘vice’ but empirical generalizations about the traits as first identified by their effects on the moral sentiments.

In the Treatise Hume details the causes of the moral sentiments, in doing so explaining why agreeable and advantageous traits prove to be the ones that generate approval. He claims that the sentiments of moral approval and disapproval are caused by some of the operations of sympathy, which is not a feeling but rather a psychological mechanism that enables one person to receive by communication the sentiments of another (more or less what we would call empathy today).

Sympathy in general operates as follows. First, observation of the outward expression of another person’s “affection” (feeling or sentiment) in his “countenance and conversation” conveys the idea of his passion into my mind. So does observing the typical cause of a passion: for example, viewing the instruments laid out for another’s surgery will evoke ideas in me of fear and pain. We at all times possess a maximally vivid and forceful impression of ourselves. According to Hume’s associationism, vivacity of one perception is automatically transferred to those others that are related to it by resemblance, contiguity, and cause and effect. Here resemblance and contiguity are primary. All human beings, regardless of their differences, are similar in bodily structure and in the types and causes of their passions. The person I observe or consider may further resemble me in more specific shared features such as character or nationality. Because of the resemblance and my contiguity to the observed person, the idea of his passion is associated in my mind with my impression of myself, and acquires great vivacity from it. The sole difference between an idea and an impression is the degree of liveliness or vivacity each possesses. So great is this acquired vivacity that the idea of his passion in my mind becomes an impression, and I actually experience the passion. When I come to share in the affections of strangers, and feel pleasure because they are pleased, as I do when I experience an aesthetic enjoyment of a well-designed ship or fertile field that is not my own, my pleasure can only be caused by sympathy (T 2.2.2–8, 3.3.1.7–8). Similarly, Hume observes, when we reflect upon a character or mental quality knowing its tendency either to the benefit or enjoyment of strangers or to their harm or uneasiness, we come to feel enjoyment when the trait is beneficial or agreeable to those strangers, and uneasiness when the trait is harmful or disagreeable to them. This reaction of ours to the tendency of a character trait to affect the sentiments of those with whom we have no special affectionate ties can only be explained by sympathy.

We greatly approve the artificial virtues (justice with respect to property, allegiance to government, and dispositions to obey the laws of nations and the rules of modesty and good manners), which (Hume argues) are inventions contrived solely for the interest of society. We approve them in all times and places, even where our own interest is not at stake, solely for their tendency to benefit the whole society of that time or place. This instance confirms that “the reflecting on the tendency of characters and mental qualities, is sufficient to give us the sentiments of approbation and blame” (T 3.3.1.9). The sympathy-generated pleasure, then, is the moral approbation we feel toward these traits of character. We find the character traits — the causes — agreeable because they are the means to ends we find agreeable as a result of sympathy. Hume extends this analysis to the approval of most of the natural virtues. Those traits of which we approve naturally (without any social contrivance), such as beneficence, clemency, and moderation, also tend to the good of individuals or all of society. So our approval of those can be explained in precisely the same way, via sympathy with the pleasure of those who receive benefit. And since the imagination is more struck by what is particular than by what is general, manifestations of the natural virtues, which directly benefit any individual to whom they are directed, are even more apt to give pleasure via sympathy than are the manifestations of justice, which may harm identifiable individuals in some cases though they contribute to a pattern of action beneficial to society as a whole (T 3.3.1.13).

8. The Common Point of View

As we saw, the moral sentiments are produced by sympathy with those affected by a trait or action. Such sympathetically-acquired feelings are distinct from our self-interested responses, and an individual of discernment learns to distinguish her moral sentiments (which are triggered by contemplating another’s character trait “in general”) from the pleasure or uneasiness she may feel when responding to a trait with reference to her “particular interest,” for example when another’s strength of character makes him a formidable opponent (T 3.1.2.4).

However, the sympathetic transmission of sentiments can vary in effectiveness depending upon the degree of resemblance and contiguity between the observer and the person with whom he sympathizes. I receive the sentiments of someone very much like me or very close to me in time or place far more strongly than I do those of someone unlike me or more remote from me in location or in history. Yet the moral assessments we make do not vary depending upon whether the person we evaluate resembles us in language, sex, or temperament, or is near or far. Indeed, our moral assessments of people remain stable even though our position with respect to them changes over time. Furthermore, sympathy only brings us people’s actual sentiments or what we believe to be their actual sentiments; yet we feel moral approval of character traits that we know produce no real happiness for anyone, because, for example, their possessor is isolated in a prison. To handle these objections to the sympathy theory, and to explain more generally how, on a sentiment-based ethical theory, moral evaluations made by one individual at different times and many individuals in a community tend to be fairly uniform, Hume claims that people do not make their moral judgments from their own individual points of view, but instead select “some common point of view, from which they might survey their object, and which might cause it to appear the same to all of them” (T 3.3.1.30). At least with respect to natural virtues and vices, this common point of view is composed of the intimate perspectives of the various individuals who have direct interactions with the person being evaluated. To make a moral evaluation I must sympathize with each of these persons in their dealings with the subject of my evaluation; the blame or praise I give as a result of this imaginative exercise is my genuine moral assessment of the subject’s character. In that assessment I also overlook the small external accidents of fortune that might render an individual’s trait ineffectual, and respond to traits that render a character typically “fitted to be beneficial to society,” even if circumstances do not permit it to cause that benefit (T 3.3.1.20). Thus I acquire by sympathy the pleasure or uneasiness that I imagine people would feel were the trait able to operate as it ordinarily does. “Experience soon teaches us this method of correcting our sentiments, or at least, of correcting our language, where the sentiments are more stubborn and inalterable” (T 3.3.1.16).

9. Artificial and Natural Virtues

The standard object of moral evaluation is a “quality of mind,” a character trait. (As we have seen, for Hume evaluation of an action is derived from evaluation of the inner quality we suppose to have given rise to it.) The typical moral judgment is that some trait, such as a particular person’s benevolence or laziness, is a virtue or a vice. A character trait, for Hume, is a psychological disposition consisting of a tendency to feel a certain sentiment or combination of sentiments, ones that often move their possessor to action. We reach a moral judgment by feeling approval or disapproval upon contemplating someone’s trait in a disinterested way from the common point of view. So moral approval is a favorable sentiment in the observer elicited by the observed person’s disposition to have certain motivating sentiments. Thus moral approval is a sentiment that is directed toward sentiments, or the dispositions to have them.

In the Treatise Hume emphasizes that “our sense of every kind of virtue is not natural; but … there are some virtues, that produce pleasure and approbation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from the circumstances and necessities of mankind” (T 3.2.1.1). He divides the virtues into those that are natural — in that our approval of them does not depend upon any cultural inventions or jointly-made social rules — and those that are artificial (dependent both for their existence as character traits and for their ethical merit on the presence of conventional rules for the common good), and he gives separate accounts of the two kinds. The traits he calls natural virtues are more refined and completed forms of those human sentiments we could expect to find even in people who belonged to no society but cooperated only within small familial groups. The traits he calls artificial virtues are the ones we need for successful impersonal cooperation; our natural sentiments are too partial to give rise to these without intervention. In the Treatise Hume includes among the artificial virtues honesty with respect to property (which he often calls equity or “justice,” though it is a strangely narrow use of the term), fidelity to promises (sometimes also listed under “justice”), allegiance to one’s government, conformity to the laws of nations (for princes), chastity (refraining from non-marital sex) and modesty (both primarily for women and girls), and good manners. A great number of individual character traits are listed as natural virtues, but the main types discussed in detail are greatness of mind (“a hearty pride, or self-esteem, if well-concealed and well-founded,” T 3.2.2.11), goodness or benevolence (an umbrella category covering generosity, gratitude, friendship, and more), and such natural abilities as prudence and wit, which, Hume argues, have a reasonably good claim to be included under the title moral virtue, though traditionally they are not. Hume does not explicitly draw a distinction between artificial and natural virtues in the moral Enquiry.

In the Treatise Hume argues in turn that the virtues of material honesty and of faithfulness to promises and contracts are artificial, not natural virtues. Both arguments fall into at least two stages: one to show that if we suppose the given character trait to exist and to win our approval without help from any cooperative social arrangement, paradoxes arise; and another, longer stage to explain how the relevant convention might have come into being and to refute those with a different genetic story. He also explains the social construction of the other artificial virtues and what social good they serve.

10. Honesty with respect to Property

10.1 The Circle

Hume offers a rather cryptic argument to show that our approval of material honesty must be the product of collaborative human effort (convention). When we approve an action, he says, we regard it merely as the sign of the motivating passion in the agent’s “mind and temper” that produced it; our evaluation of the action is derived from our assessment of this inner motive. Therefore all actions deemed virtuous derive their goodness only from virtuous motives — motives we approve. It follows from this that the motive that originally “bestows a merit on any action” can never be moral approval of that action (awareness of its virtue), but must be a non-moral, motivating psychological state — that is, a state distinct from the “regard to the virtue” of an action (moral approval or disapproval) (T 3.2.1.4). For if the virtue-bestowing motive of the action were the agent’s sense that the act would be virtuous to do — if that were why he did it, and why we approved it — then we would be reasoning in a vicious circle: we would approve of the action derivatively, because we approve of the agent’s motive, and this motive would consist of approval of the action, which can only be based on approval of a motive... The basis of our approval could not be specified. For every virtue, therefore, there must be some non-moral motive that characteristically motivates actions expressive of that virtue, which motive, by eliciting our approval, makes the actions so motivated virtuous. The virtue of an action of this species would be established by its being done from this non-moral motive, and only then could an agent also or alternatively be moved so to act by her derivative concern for the virtue of the act. However, Hume observes that there is no morally approved (and so virtue-bestowing), non-moral motive of honest action. The only approved, reliable motive that we can find for acts of “equity” is a moral one, the sense of virtue or “regard to the honesty” of the actions. The honest individual repays a loan not (merely) out of self-interest or concern for the well-being of the lender (who may be a “profligate debauchee” who will reap only harm from his possessions), but from a “regard to justice, and abhorrence of villainy and knavery” (T 3.2.1.9, 13). This, however, is “evident sophistry and reasoning in a circle…” Now nature cannot have “establish’d a sophistry, and render’d it necessary and unavoidable…”; therefore, “the sense of justice and injustice is not deriv’d from nature, but arises artificially… from education, and human conventions” (T 3.2.1.17). Whatever, exactly, the logic of this argument is supposed to be, Hume’s intent is to show that if we imagine equity to be a natural virtue we commit ourselves to a sophistry, and therefore honesty is instead man-made.

Hume offers an account of the genesis of the social convention that creates honesty with respect to property, and this is meant to cope in some way with the circularity he identifies. How it does so is a matter of interpretive controversy, as we will see.

10.2 The Origin of Material Honesty

Hume next poses two questions about the rules of ownership of property and the associated virtue of material honesty: what is the artifice by which human beings create them, and why do we attribute moral goodness and evil to the observance and neglect of these rules?

By nature human beings have many desires but are individually ill-equipped with strength, natural weapons, or natural skills to satisfy them. We can remedy these natural defects by means of social cooperation: shared strength, division of labor, and mutual aid in times of individual weakness. It occurs to people to form a society as a consequence of their experience with the small family groups into which they are born, groups united initially by sexual attraction and familial love, but in time demonstrating the many practical advantages of working together with others. However, in the conditions of moderate scarcity in which we find ourselves, and given the portable nature of the goods we desire, our untrammeled greed and naturally “confined generosity” (generosity to those dear to us in preference to others) tends to create conflict or undermine cooperation, destroying collaborative arrangements among people who are not united by ties of affection, and leaving us all materially poor. No remedy for this natural partiality is to be found in “our natural uncultivated ideas of morality” (T 3.2.2.8); an invention is needed.

Hume argues that we create the rules of ownership of property originally in order to satisfy our avidity for possessions for ourselves and our loved ones, by linking material goods more securely to particular individuals so as to avoid conflict. Within small groups of cooperators, individuals signal to one another a willingness to conform to a simple rule: to refrain from the material goods others come to possess by labor or good fortune, provided those others will observe the same restraint toward them. (This rule will in time require more detail: specific rules determining who may enjoy which goods initially and how goods may be transferred.) This signalling is not a promise (which cannot occur without another, similar convention), but an expression of conditional intention. The usefulness of such a custom is so obvious that others will soon catch on and express a similar intention, and the rest will fall in line. The convention develops tacitly, as do conventions of language and money. When an individual within such a small society violates this rule, the others are aware of it and exclude the offender from their cooperative activities. Once the convention is in place, justice (of this sort) is defined as conformity with the convention, injustice as violation of it; indeed, the convention defines property rights, ownership, financial obligation, theft, and related concepts, which had no application before the convention was introduced. So useful and obvious is this invention that human beings would not live for long in isolated family groups or in fluctuating larger groups with unstable possession of goods; their ingenuity would quickly enable them to invent property, so as to reap the substantial economic benefits of cooperation in larger groups in which there would be reliable possession of the product, and they would thus better satisfy their powerful natural greed by regulating it with rules of justice.

Greed, and more broadly, self-interest, is the motive for inventing property; but we need a further explanation why we think of justice (adherence to the rules of ownership) as virtuous, and injustice (their violation) as vicious. Hume accounts for the moralization of property as follows. As our society grows larger, we may cease to see our own property violations as a threat to the continued existence of a stable economic community, and this reduces our incentive to conform. But when we consider violations by others, we partake by sympathy in the uneasiness these violations cause to their victims and all of society. Such disinterested uneasiness, and the concomitant pleasure we feel on contemplating the public benefits of adherence, are instances of moral disapproval and approval. We extend these feelings to our own behavior as a result of general rules. This process is “forwarded by the artifice of politicians” (T 3.2.2.25), who assist nature by cultivating widespread esteem for justice and abhorrence of injustice in order to govern more easily. Private education assists in this further artifice. Thus material honesty becomes a virtue.

10.3 The Motive of Honest Actions

Does this account resolve the circularity problem? Is there any non-moral motive of honest action? Some interpreters say yes, it is greed redirected, which removes the circle. But this presents two difficulties: first, our greed is not in fact best satisfied by just action in every case, and second, Hume denies that this motive is approved. Some interpret Hume as coping with the first difficulty by supposing that politicians and parents deceive us into thinking, falsely, that every individual just act advances the interests of the agent; or they claim that Hume himself mistakenly thought so, at least in the Treatise (see Baron, Haakonssen, and Gauthier). Others claim that Hume identifies a non-moral motive of honest action (albeit an artificial one) other than redirected greed, such as a disposition to treat the rules of justice as themselves reason-giving (Darwall) or having a policy of conforming to the rules of justice as a system (Garrett). Still others say there is no non-moral motive of honest action, and Hume escapes from the circle by relaxing this ostensibly universal requirement on virtuous types of behavior, limiting it to the naturally virtuous kinds. These interpreters either claim that there is no particular motive needed to evoke approval for conformity to the rules of property — mere behavior is enough (Mackie) — or that we approve of a motivating form of the moral sentiment itself, the sense of duty (Cohon).

Hume’s genetic account of property is striking for its lack of patriarchal assumptions about the family, its explicit denial that the creation of ownership does or can depend on any promise or contract, and its concept of convention as an informal practice of mutual compromise for mutual advantage that arises incrementally and entirely informally, without the use of central authority or force.

11. Fidelity to Promises

Fidelity is the virtue of being disposed to fulfill promises and contracts. Hume has in mind promises made “at arm’s length” that parties undertake to promote their own interest, not affectionate exchanges of favors between friends. While he identifies the same circularity puzzle about the approved motive of fidelity that he tackles at length in connection with honesty, in the case of fidelity he concentrates on a different conundrum that arises with the misguided attempt to analyze fidelity as a non-conventional (natural) virtue. Unlike Hobbes and Locke, who help themselves to the concept of a promise or contract in their imagined state of nature, Hume argues that the performative utterance “I promise” would be unintelligible in the absence of background social conventions, and that the moral obligation of a promise is dependent upon such conventions as well.

Suppose the practice of giving and receiving promises did not depend on a socially-defined convention. In that case, what could we mean by the utterances we use to make them, and what would be the origin of our obligation to fulfill them? Where the words are used (uncharacteristically) in a way that does not purport to reveal the agent’s will (as when the person is joking or play-acting), we do not think a promise is really being made; we only take a speaker to have promised, and so to be bound to perform, if he understands the words he uses, in particular as purporting to obligate him. Thus for effective use there must be some act of the speaker’s mind expressed by the special phrase “I promise” and its synonyms, and our moral obligation results from this act of the mind. (This seems to be Hobbes’s assumption in Leviathan, where the implicit signs of covenant — as distinct from the explicit ones — are clear signs of the person’s will.) The requisite mental act or mental state, though, could not be one of mere desire or resolution to act, since it does not follow from our desiring or resolving to act that we are morally obligated to do so; nor could it be the volition to act, since that does not come into being ahead of time when we promise, but only when the time comes to act. And of course, one can promise successfully (incur obligation by promising) even though one has no intention to perform; so the mental act requisite to obligation is not the intention to perform. The only likely act of mind that might be expressed in a promise is a mental act of willing to be obligated to perform the promised action, as this conforms to our common view that we bind ourselves by choosing to be bound.

But, Hume argues, it is absurd to think that one can actually bring an obligation into existence by willing to be obligated. What makes an action obligatory is that its omission is disapproved by unbiased observers. But no act of will within an agent can directly change a previously neutral act into one that provokes moral disapproval in observers (even in the agent herself). Sentiments are not subject to such voluntary control. Even on a moral rationalist view the thesis would be absurd: to create a new obligation would be to change the abstract relations in which actions and persons stand to one another, and one cannot do this by performing in one’s own mind an act of willing such a relation to exist. Thus, there is no such act of the mind. Even if people in their natural (pre-conventional) condition “cou’d perceive each other’s thoughts by intuition,” they could not understand one another to bind themselves by any act of promising, and could not be obligated thereby. Since the necessary condition for a natural obligation of promises cannot be fulfilled, we may conclude that this obligation is instead the product of group invention to serve the interests of society.

Promises are invented in order to build upon the advantages afforded by property. The invention of mere ownership suffices to make possession stable. The introduction of transfer by consent permits some trade, but so far only simultaneous swapping of visible commodities. Great advantages could be gained by all if people could be counted on to provide goods or services later for benefits given now, or exchange goods that are distant or described generically. But for people without the capacity to obligate themselves to future action, such exchanges would depend upon the party who performs second doing so out of gratitude alone; and that motive cannot generally be relied on in self-interested transactions. However, we can devise better ways to satisfy our appetites “in an oblique and artificial manner...” (T 3.2.5.9). First, people can easily recognize that additional kinds of mutual exchanges would serve their interests. They need only express this interest to one another in order to encourage everyone to invent and to keep such agreements. They devise a form of words to mark these new sorts of exchanges (and distinguish them from the generous reciprocal acts of friendship and gratitude). When someone utters this form of words, he is understood to express a resolution to do the action in question, and he “subjects himself to the penalty of never being trusted again in case of failure” (T 3.2.5.10), a penalty made possible by the practice of the group, who enforce the requirement to keep promises by the simple expedient of refusing to contract with those whose word cannot be trusted . This “concert or convention” (ibid.) alters human motives to act. One is moved by self-interest to give the promising sign (in order to obtain the other party’s cooperation), and once one has given it, self-interest demands that one do what one promised to do so as to insure that people will exchange promises with one in the future. Some interpreters say that this enlightened self-interest remains the only motive for keeping one’s promise, once the practice of promising has been created. But Hume says the sentiment of morals comes to play the same role in promise-keeping that it does in the development of honesty with respect to property (T 3.2.5.12); so there is evidence he thinks the moral sentiment not only becomes “annex’d” to promise-keeping but further motivates it. In larger, more anonymous communities, a further incentive is needed besides the fear of exclusion; and a sentiment of moral approval of promise-keeping arises as the result of sympathy with all who benefit from the practice, aided by a “second artifice,” the well-meaning psychological manipulation of the people by parents and politicians, which yields a near-universal admiration of fidelity and shame at breaking one’s word (T 3.2.5.12). This may provide a moral motive for promise-keeping even in anonymous transactions.

12. Allegiance to Government

A small society can maintain a subsistence-level economy without any dominion of some people over others, relying entirely on voluntary compliance with conventions of ownership, transfer of goods, and keeping of agreements, and relying on exclusion as the sole means of enforcement. But an increase in population and/or material productivity, Hume thinks, tends to stimulate a destabilizing rate of defection from the rules: more luxury goods greatly increase the temptation to act unjustly, and more anonymous transactions make it seem likely that one will get away with it. Though people are aware that injustice is destructive of social cooperation and so ultimately detrimental to their own interests, this knowledge will not enable them to resist such strong temptation, because of an inherent human weakness: we are more powerfully drawn to a near-term good even when we know we will pay for it with the loss of a greater long-term good. This creates the need for government to enforce the rules of property and promise (the “laws of nature,” as Hume sometimes rather ironically calls them, since on his view they are not natural). This is the reason for the invention of government. Once in power, rulers can also make legitimate use of their authority to resolve disputes over just what the rules of justice require in particular cases, and to carry out projects for the common good such as building roads and dredging harbors.

Hume thinks it unnecessary to prove that allegiance to government is the product of convention and not mere nature, since governments are obviously social creations. But he does need to explain the creation of governments and how they solve the problem he describes. He speculates that people who are unaccustomed to subordination in daily life might draw the idea for government from their experience of wars with other societies, when they must appoint a temporary commander. To overcome the preference for immediate gain over long-term security, the people will need to arrange social circumstances so that the conformity to justice is in people’s immediate interest. This cannot be done with respect to all the people, but it can be done for a few. So the people select magistrates (judges, kings, and the like) and so position them (presumably with respect to rank and wealth) that it will be in those magistrates’ immediate interest not only to obey but to enforce the rules of justice throughout society. Hume is vague about the incentives of the magistrates, but apparently they are so pleased with their own share of wealth and status that they are not tempted by the possessions of others; and since they are “indifferent… to the greatest part of the state,” they have no incentive to assist anyone in any crimes (T3.2.7.6). Thus the magistrates’ most immediate interest lies in preserving their own status and wealth by protecting society. (Perhaps more directly, they stand to lose their favored status if they are found by the people not to enforce the rules of justice.)

It is possible for the people to agree to appoint magistrates in spite of the incurable human attraction to the proximal good even when smaller than a remote good, because this predilection only takes effect when the lesser good is immediately at hand. When considering two future goods, people always prefer the greater, and make decisions accordingly. So looking to the future, people can decide now to empower magistrates to force them to conform to the rules of justice in the time to come so as to preserve society. When the time comes to obey and individuals are tempted to violate the rules, the long-range threat this poses to society may not move them to desist, but the immediate threat of punishment by the magistrates will.

We initially obey our magistrates from self-interest. But once government is instituted, we come to have a moral obligation to obey our governors; this is another artificial duty that needs to be explained. On Hume’s view it is independent of the obligation of promises. We are bound to our promises and to obey the magistrates’ commands on parallel grounds: because both kinds of conformity are so manifestly beneficial for all. Governors merely insure that the rules of justice are generally obeyed in the sort of society where purely voluntary conventions would otherwise break down. As in the case of fidelity to promises, the character trait of allegiance to our governors generates sympathy with its beneficiaries throughout society, making us approve the trait as a virtue.

The duty of allegiance to our present governors does not depend upon their or their ancestors’ divine right to govern, Hume says, nor on any promise we have made to them or any contract that transfers rights to them, but rather on the general social value of having a government. Rulers thus need not be chosen by the people in order to be legitimate. Consequently, who is the ruler will often be a matter of salience and imaginative association; and it will be no ground for legitimate rebellion that a ruler was selected arbitrarily. Rulers identified by long possession of authority, present possession, conquest, succession, or positive law will be suitably salient and so legitimate, provided their rule tends to the common good. Although governments exist to serve the interests of their people, changing magistrates and forms of government for the sake of small advantages to the public would yield disorder and upheaval, defeating the purpose of government; so our duty of allegiance forbids this. A government that maintains conditions preferable to what they would be without it retains its legitimacy and may not rightly be overthrown. But rebellion against a cruel tyranny is no violation of our duty of allegiance, and may rightly be undertaken.

Hume does advocate some forms of government as being preferable to others, particularly in his Essays. Governments structured by laws are superior to those controlled by the edicts of rulers or ruling bodies (“That Politics May Be Reduced to a Science”). Representative democracy is superior to direct democracy, and “free” (popular) governments are more hospitable to trade than “absolute” governments (ibid.). Hume speculates that a perfect government would be a representative democracy of property-holders with division of powers and some features of federalism (“Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth”). He defends his preferences by arguing that certain forms of government are less prone to corruption, faction (with the concomitant threat of civil war), and oppressive treatment of the people than others; that is, they are more likely to enforce the rules of justice, adjudicate fairly, and encourage peace and prosperity.

Hume famously criticizes the social contract theory of political obligation. According to his own theory, our duty to obey our governors is not reducible to an instance of our duty to fulfill promises, but arises separately though in a way parallel to the genesis of that duty. Hume denies that any native citizen or subject in his own day has made even a tacit promise to obey the government, given that citizens do not think they did any such thing, but rather think they are born to obey it. Even a tacit contract requires that the will be engaged, and we have no memory of this; nor do governments refrain from punishing disloyalty in citizens who have given no tacit promise.

13. The Natural Virtues

In the Treatise Hume’s principle interest in the natural virtues lies in explaining the causes that make us approve them. The mechanism of sympathy ultimately accounts for this approval and the corresponding disapproval of the natural vices. Sympathy also explains our approval of the artificial virtues; the difference is that we approve of those as a result of sympathy with the cumulative effects produced by the general practice of the artificial virtues on the whole of society (individual acts of justice not always producing pleasure for anyone); whereas we approve each individual exercise of such natural virtues as gratitude and friendship because we sympathize with those who are affected by each such action when we consider it from the common point of view. As we saw, he argues that the traits of which we approve fall into four groups: traits immediately agreeable to their possessor or to others, and traits advantageous to their possessor or to others. In these four groups of approved traits, our approval arises as the result of sympathy bringing into our minds the pleasure that the trait produces for its possessor or for others (with one minor exception). This is especially clear with such self-regarding virtues as prudence and industry, which we approve even when they occur in individuals who provide no benefit to us observers; this can only be explained by our sympathy with the benefits that prudence and industry bring to their possessors.

According to Hume, different levels and manifestations of the passions of pride and humility make for virtue or for vice. An obvious and “over-weaning conceit” is disapproved by any observer (is a vice) (T 3.3.2.1); while a well-founded but concealed self-esteem is approved (is a virtue). Hume explains these opposite reactions to such closely related character traits by means of the interplay of the observer’s sympathy with a distinct psychological mechanism he calls comparison. The mechanism of comparison juxtaposes a sympathetically-communicated sentiment with the observer’s own inherent feeling, causing the observer to feel a sentiment opposite to the one she observes in another (pleasure if the other is suffering, pain if the other is pleased) when the sympathetically-communicated sentiment is not too strong. A person who displays excessive pride irritates others because, while others come to feel this person’s pleasant sentiment of pride (to some degree) via sympathy, they also feel a greater uneasiness as a result of comparing that great pride (in whose objects they do not believe) with their own lesser pride in themselves; this is why conceit is a vice. Self-esteem founded on an accurate assessment of one’s strengths and politely concealed from others, though, is both agreeable and advantageous to its possessor without being distressing to others, and so is generally approved. (Thus the professed preference of Christians for humility over self-esteem does not accord with the judgments of most observers.) Although excessive pride is a natural vice and self-esteem a natural virtue, human beings in society create the artificial virtue of good breeding (adherence to customs of slightly exaggerated mutual deference in accordance with social rank) to enable us each to conceal our own pride easily so that it does not shock the pride of others.

Courage and military heroism are also forms of pride. Though the student of history can see that military ambition has mostly been disadvantageous to human society, when we contemplate the “dazling” character of the hero, immediate sympathy irresistibly leads us to approve it (T 3.3.2.15).

Our approval of those traits that may be grouped together under the heading of goodness and benevolence, such as generosity, humanity, compassion, and gratitude, arises from sympathy with people in the individual’s “narrow circle” of friends and associates, since, given natural human selfishness, we cannot expect people’s concerns to extend farther (T 3.3.3.2). By adopting the common point of view we correct for the distortions of sympathy by entering into the feelings of those close to the person being evaluated even if they are remote from us. The vice of cruelty is most loathed because the suffering of the person’s victims that reaches us via sympathy readily becomes hatred of the perpetrator.

Although natural abilities of the mind are not traditionally classified as moral virtues and vices, the difference between these types of traits is unimportant, Hume argues. Intelligence, good judgment, application, eloquence, and wit are also mental qualities that bring individuals the approbation of others, and their absence is disapproved. As is the case with many of the traditionally-recognized virtues, the various natural abilities are approved either because they are useful to their possessor or because they are immediately agreeable to others. It is sometimes argued that moral virtues are unlike natural abilities in that the latter are involuntary, but Hume argues that many traditional moral virtues are involuntary as well. The sole difference is that the prospect of reward or punishment can induce people to act as the morally virtuous would (as justice requires, for example), but cannot induce them to act as if they had the natural abilities.

14. Differences between the Treatise and the Moral Enquiry

Late in his life Hume deemed the Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals his best work, and in style it is a model of elegance and subtlety. His method in that work differs from that of the Treatise: instead of explicating the nature of virtue and vice and our knowledge of them in terms of underlying features of the human mind, he proposes to collect all the traits we know from common sense to be virtues and vices, observe what those in each group have in common, and from that observation discover the “foundation of ethics” (EPM 1.10). The conclusions largely coincide with those of the Treatise. Some topics in the Treatise are handled more fully in the moral Enquiry; for example Hume’s account of the motive to just action is enriched by his discussion of a challenge from a “sensible knave.” However, without the detailed background theories of the mind, the passions, motivation to action, and social convention presented in the Treatise, and without any substitute for them, some of the conclusions of the moral Enquiry stand unsupported.

In the latter work, Hume’s main argument that reason alone is not adequate to yield moral evaluations (in Appendix 1) depends on his having demonstrated throughout the book that at least one foundation of moral praise lies in the usefulness to society of the praised character trait. We use reason extensively to learn the effects of various traits and to identify the useful and pernicious ones. But utility and disutility are merely means; were we indifferent to the weal and woe of mankind, we would feel equally indifferent to the traits that promote those ends. Therefore there must be some sentiment that makes us favor the one over the other. This could only be humanity, “a feeling for the happiness of mankind, and resentment of their misery” (EPM App. 1.3). This argument presupposes that the moral evaluations we make are themselves the expression of sentiment rather than reason alone. (The alternative position would be that while of course we do feel approval and disapproval for vice and virtue, the judgment as to which is which is itself the deliverance of reason.) So Hume appends some arguments directed against the hypothesis of moral rationalism. One of these is an enriched version of the argument of Treatise 3.1.1 that neither demonstrative nor causal reasoning has moral distinctions as its proper object, since moral vice and virtue cannot plausibly be analyzed as either facts or relations. He adds that while in our reasonings we start from the knowledge of relations or facts and infer some previously-unknown relation or fact, moral evaluation cannot proceed until all the relevant facts and relations are already known. At that point, there is nothing further for reason to do; therefore moral evaluation is not the work of reason alone but of another faculty. He bolsters this line of argument by expanding his Treatise analogy between moral and aesthetic judgment, arguing that just as our appreciation of beauty awaits full information about the object but requires the further contribution of taste, so in moral evaluation our assessment of merit or villainy awaits full knowledge of the person and situation but requires the further contribution of approbation or disapprobation. He also offers the argument that since the chain of reasons why one acts must finally stop at something that is “desirable on its own account… because of its immediate accord or agreement with sentiment…” (EPM App.1.19), sentiment is needed to account for ultimate human ends; and since virtue is an end, sentiment and not reason alone must distinguish moral good and evil.

In the moral Enquiry Hume omits all arguments to show that reason alone does not move us to act; so the Representation Argument about the irrelevance of reason to passions and actions is absent. Without it he has no support for his direct argument that moral goodness and evil are not identical with reasonableness and unreasonableness, which relies on it for its key premise; and that too is absent from EPM. On the whole in EPM Hume does not appeal to the thesis that reason cannot produce motives in order to show that morals are not derived from reason alone, but limits himself to the epistemic and descriptive arguments showing that reason alone cannot discern virtue and vice in order to reject ethical rationalism in favor of sentimentalism. However, at Appendix I.21 he does assert (without support) that “Reason, being cool and disengaged, is no motive to action,” and perhaps this is intended to be a premise in a revised version of the famous argument that reason cannot produce motives but morals can, though what he writes here is tantalizingly different from that argument as it appears repeatedly in the Treatise.

Why did Hume omit the more fundamental arguments for the motivational inertia of reason? He may have reconsidered and rejected them. For example, he may have given up his undefended claim that passions have no representative character, a premise of the Representation Argument on which, as we saw, some of his fundamental anti-rationalist arguments depend. Or he may have retained these views but opted not to appeal to anything so arcane in a work aimed at a broader audience and intended to be as accessible as possible. The moral Enquiry makes no use of ideas and impressions, and so no arguments that depend on that distinction can be offered there, including the Representation Argument. Apparently Hume thought he could show that reason and sentiment rule different domains without using those arguments.

Thus, not surprisingly, the causal analysis of sympathy as a mechanism of vivacity-transferal from the impression of the self to the ideas of the sentiments of others is entirely omitted from the moral Enquiry. Hume still appeals to sympathy there to explain the origin of all moral approval and disapproval, but he explains our sympathy with others simply as a manifestation of the sentiment of humanity, which is given more prominence. He is still concerned about the objection that sympathetically-acquired sentiments vary with spatial and temporal distance from the object of evaluation while moral assessments do not; so he addresses it in the moral Enquiry as well, and resolves it by appealing once again to the common point of view. In the Enquiry he places more emphasis on sympathy with the interests of the whole of society, in part achieved by conversation using shared moral vocabulary, as a way to correct our initial sentiments to make them genuinely moral (Taylor 2002). He also attends more explicitly to the role of reason and reflection in moral evaluation. Some interpreters see him as offering an account of how to arrive at reliable moral judgment superior to that in the Treatise (Taylor 2015).

The distinction between artificial and natural virtues that dominates the virtue ethics of the Treatise is almost entirely absent from the moral Enquiry; the term ‘artificial’ occurs in the latter only once in a footnote. Gone are the paradoxes of property and promises intended to prove that particular virtues are devised on purpose; also missing is what some commentators think Hume’s most original contribution to the theory of justice, his account of convention. Yet Hume briefly sketches part of the same quasi-historical account of the origin of justice that he gives in the Treatise; and while the emphasis has shifted, Hume not only tries to show that justice has merit only because of its beneficial consequences, but that “public utility is the sole origin of justice” — were we not to find it useful (and in some conditions we might not) we would not even have such a thing (EPM 3.1.1). While any explanation of this shift and these omissions is merely speculative, here it seems that Hume does not change his mind about the arguments of the Treatise but chooses to lead the reader to the same conclusions by more subtle and indirect means while avoiding provocative claims.

In the moral Enquiry Hume is more explicit about what he takes to be the errors of Christian (or, more cautiously, Roman Catholic) moralists. Not only have they elevated craven humility to the status of a virtue, which he hints in the Treatise is a mistake, but they also favor penance, fasting, and other “monkish virtues” that are in fact disapproved by all reasonable folk for their uselessness and disagreeableness, and so are in fact vices.

Bibliography

Primary Sources: Works by Hume

  • A Treatise of Human Nature: A Critical Edition, David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (eds.), Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2007. (References to this work start with T and are followed by Book, Part, Section and paragraph number, in parentheses in the text.)
  • A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford Philosophical Texts), David Fate Norton and Mary J. Norton (eds.), Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2000.
  • A Treatise of Human Nature, L. A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), 2nd ed. revised by P.H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975.
  • An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, Tom L. Beauchamp (ed.) (The Claredon Edition of the Works of David Hume), Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1998. (References to this work start with EPM and are followed by Part, Section (if any), and paragraph number, in parentheses within the text.)
  • Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, in Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and concerning the Principles of Morals, L. A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), 3rd ed revised by P. H. Nidditch, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975
  • Essays Moral, Political, and Literary, Eugene Miller (ed.), Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1985.

Secondary Sources

  • Abramson, Kate, 2001, “Sympathy and the Project of Hume’s Second Enquiry,” Archiv für Geschichte der Phiosophie, 83(1): 45–80.
  • Ainslie, Donald C. and Butler, Annemarie, 2015, The Cambridge Companion to Hume’s Treatise, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Árdal, Páll, 1966, Passion and Value in Hume’s Treatise, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press; 2nd edition, revised, 1989.
  • –––, 1977a, “Another Look at Hume’s Account of Moral Evaluation,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 15: 405–421.
  • –––, 1977b, “Convention and Value,” in David Hume: Bicentenary Papers, G.P. Morice (ed.), Austin: University of Texas Press, pp. 51–68.
  • Baier, Annette C., 1988, “Hume’s Account of Social Artifice — Its Origins and Originality,” Ethics, 98: 757–778.
  • –––, 1991, A Progress of Sentiments, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 2010, The Cautious Jealous Virtue: Hume on Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Baron, Marcia, 1982, “Hume’s Noble Lie: An Account of His Artificial Virtues,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 12: 539–55.
  • Blackburn, Simon, 1993, “Hume on the Mezzanine Level,” Hume Studies, 19 (2): 273–288.
  • Botros, Sophie, 2006, Hume, Reason and Morality: A legacy of contradiction, London and New York: Routledge.
  • Bricke, John, 1996, Mind and Morality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Brown, Charlotte, 1988, “Is Hume an Internalist?” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 26: 69–87.
  • Capaldi, Nicholas, 1975, David Hume: The Newtonian Philosopher, Boston: Twayne Publishing.
  • –––, 1989, Hume’s Place in Moral Philosophy, New York: Peter Lang.
  • Chappell, V.C. (ed.), 1996, Hume: A Collection of Critical Essays, Garden City, NY: Doubleday.
  • Cohon, Rachel, 1997a, “The Common Point of View in Hume’s Ethics,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57 (4): 827–850.
  • –––, 1997b, “Hume’s Difficulty with the Virtue of Honesty,” Hume Studies, 23 (1): 91–112.
  • –––, 2001a, “The Shackles of Virtue: Hume on Allegiance to Government,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 18 (4): 393–413.
  • ––– (ed.), 2001b, Hume: Moral and Political Philosophy, Aldershot, England and Burlington, Vermont: Dartmouth/Ashgate.
  • –––, 2008, Hume’s Morality: Feeling and Fabrication, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Coventry, Angela and Sager, Alexander, 2019, The Humean Mind, New York: Routledge.
  • Darwall, Stephen, 1995, The British Moralists and the Internal ‘Ought’, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Dees, Richard H., 1997, “Hume on the Characters of Virtue,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 35 (1): 45–65.
  • Falk, W.D., 1976, “Hume on Is and Ought,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 6: 359–378.
  • Flew, Antony, 1963, “On the Interpretation of Hume,”Philosophy, 38: 178–181.
  • Foot, Philippa, 1963, “Hume on Moral Judgment,” in D. Pears (ed.), David Hume: A Symposium, London: St. Martin’s Press, pp. 74–80.
  • Forbes, Duncan, 1975, Hume’s Philosophical Politics, Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1977, “Hume’s Science of Politics” in David Hume: Bicentenary Papers, G.P. Morice (ed.), Austin, TX: University of Texas Press, pp. 39–50.
  • Garrett, Don, 1997, Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2007, “The First Motive to Justice: Hume’s Circle Argument Squared,” Hume Studies, 33 (2): 257–288.
  • Gauthier, David, 1979, “David Hume, Contractarian,” The Philosophical Review, 88: 3–38.
  • –––, 1992, “Artificial Virtues and the Sensible Knave,” Hume Studies, 18 (2): 401–427.
  • Gill, Michael, 2000, “Hume’s Progressive View of Human Nature,” Hume Studies, 26 (1): 87–108.
  • –––, 2006, The British Moralists on Human Nature and the Birth of Secular Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Haakonssen, Knud, 1981, The Science of a Legislator: The Natural Jurisprudence of David Hume and Adam Smith, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Hampton, Jean, 1995, “Does Hume Have an Instrumental Conception of Practical Reason?”, Hume Studies, 21 (1): 57–74.
  • Harris, James A., 2015, Hume: An Intellectual Biography, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Harrison, Jonathan, 1981, Hume’s Theory of Justice, Oxford, Clarendon Press.
  • –––, 1976, Hume’s Moral Epistemology, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Hudson, W.D., 1964, “Hume on Is and Ought,” The Philosophical Quaterly, 14: 246–252.
  • Hunter Geoffrey, 1962, “Hume on Is and Ought,” Philosophy, 37: 148–152.
  • –––, 1963, “Reply to Professor Flew,” Philosophy, 38: 182–184.
  • Hutcheson, Francis, 1742, Illustrations on the Moral Sense, Bernard Peach (ed.), Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Jensen, Henning, 1977, “Hume on Moral Agreement,” Mind, 86: 497–513.
  • Kail, P. J. E., 2007, Projection and Realism in Hume’s Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Korsgaard, Christine M., 1999, “The General Point of View: Love and Moral Approval in Hume’s Ethics,” Hume Studies, 25 (1/2): 3–41.
  • Livingston, Donald W., 1984, Hume’s Philosophy of Common Life, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Loeb, Louis, 1977, “Hume’s Moral Sentiments and the Structure of the Treatise,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 15: 395–403.
  • MacIntyre, A.C., 1959, “Hume on ‘Is’ and ‘Ought’,” Philosophical Review, 68: 451–468.
  • Mackie, J.L., 1980, Hume’s Moral Theory, London: Routledge.
  • Magri, Tito, 1996, “Natural Obligation and Normative Motivation in Hume’s Treatise,” Hume Studies, 22 (2): 231–253.
  • McIntyre, Jane, 1990, “Character: A Humean Account,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 7: 193–206.
  • Miller, David, 1981, Philosophy and Ideology in Hume’s Political Thought, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Millgram, Elijah, 1995, “Was Hume a Humean?,” Hume Studies, 21 (1): 75–93.
  • Morice, G. P. (ed.), 1977, David Hume: Bicentenary Papers, Austin, TX: University of Texas Press.
  • Norton, David Fate, 1982, David Hume: Common-Sense Moralist, Sceptical Metaphysician, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • –––, 1985, “Hume’s Moral Ontology,” Hume Studies, 11 (Supplement): 189–214.
  • ––– (ed.), 1993, The Cambridge Companion to Hume, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 1993a, “Hume, Human Nature, and the Foundations of Morality,” in Fate 1993, pp. 148–182.
  • Norton, David Fate, and Jacqueline Taylor (eds.), 2008, The Cambridge Companion to Hume, second edition, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Persson, Ingmar, 1997, “Hume — Not a ‘Humean’ about Motivation,” History of Philosophy Quarterly, 14 (2): 189–206.
  • Radcliffe, Elizabeth S., 1996, “How Does the Humean Sense of Duty Motivate?,” Journal of the History of Philosophy, 34 (3): 383–407.
  • –––, 1997, “Kantian Tunes on a Humean Instrument: Why Hume is not Really a Skeptic about Practical Reasoning,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 27 (2): 247–270.
  • ––– (ed.), 2008, A Companion to Hume, Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Raphael, D.D. (ed.), 1991, British Moralsits 1650 — 1800, Volume I, Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Schneewind, J. B., 1998, The Invention of Autonomy, Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.
  • Setiya, Kieran, 2016, “Hume on Practical Reason,” reprinted in Practical Knowledge: Selected Essays, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Smith, Norman Kemp, 1941, The Philosophy of David Hume, London: Macmillian.
  • Snare, Francis, 1991, Morals, Motivation and Convention, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Stewart, John B., 1992, Opinion and Reform in Hume’s Political Philosophy, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Stroud, Barry, 1977, Hume, London: Routledge.
  • –––, 1993, “Gliding or ‘Staining’ The World with ‘Sentiments’ and ‘Phantasms,’” Hume Studies, 19 (2): 253–272.
  • Sturgeon, Nicholas, 2001, “Moral Skepticism and Moral Naturalism in Hume’s Treatise,” Hume Studies, 21 (1): 3–83.
  • Swain, Corliss, 1992, “Passionate Objectivity,” Noûs, 26 (4): 465–490.
  • Taylor, Jacqueline, 1998, “Justice and the Foundations of Social Morality in Hume’s Treatise,” Hume Studies, 24 (1): 5–30.
  • –––, 2002, “Hume on the Standard of Virtue,” Journal of Ethics, 6: 43–62.
  • –––, 2015, Reflecting Subjects: Passion, Sympathy and Society in Hume’s Philosophy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Traiger, Saul (ed.), 2006, The Blackwell Guide to Hume’s Treatise, Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
  • Whelan, Frederick, 1981, Order and Artifice in Hume’s Political Philosophy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Wiggins, David, 1998, “A Sensible Subjectivism?” in Needs, Values, Truth, 3rd edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 185–210.

Copyright © 2018 by
Rachel Cohon <rcohon@albany.edu> “

 

 

 

                                                      X 

 

Objectivist Professor Stephen Hicks, like all Randians, would counterargue against Jordan Peterson that the human worship of and glorification of the human intellect in and of itself is the source of Luciferian evil, or is a source of general evil in the world.

Hicks the atheist and conservative secular humanist does not believe in God or Lucifer nor in spiritual good or spiritual evil. He talks repeatedly about how each person possesses a powerful intellect and is able to reason and think for herself. It is not too far a leap from there to my stance that each of the average-abilitied masses are laden with intelligence and talent, which they should and can maverize as individuators.

Neither Hicks or I accept that intellect qua intellect is inherently evil let alone leading to Proud Luciferian lifestyle for human intellect worshipers, proud and vain, that putative state of evil so castigated by Jordan Peterson.

This is not to deny that wicked humans and geniuses like Stalin, Mao, and Hitler, used their intellect and reasoning faculties to bring about great wickedness and harm in the world. Any tool can be used for good or for evil purposes.

I hope that Hicks would agree with me that the passions, (not to be repressed, nor allowed to run amok, especially in the pack setting), if not trained, limited, and redirected, by the individual agent, responsible, moral and conscience-guided, are the major source of evil unleashed in the world. Hicks would refer to it as social or natural evil, and I would add that such evils, are spiritual at the bottom of each.

Hicks wrote Explaining Postmodernism (Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucalt). I will quote a couple of paragraphs from Page 9 of his Expanded Edition, and then comment on them. My objective is to demonstrate how Hicks and Objectivists link human individualism and reasoning with ethics, liberty, prosperity, human advancement and the Enlightenment, that the sovereign individual, using his intellect, his merited pride, and by asserting his egoistic prerogative is not only a net good for the world, but the rational individualist is the source of goodness in action being carried out on earth, the source of human improvement and happiness, and this is quite the opposite of what Jordan Peterson is coming with.

Here are Hick’s paragraphs: Article 23: “The modern philosophers disagreed among themselves about many issues, but their core agreements outweighed the disagreements. Descartes’s account of reason, for example is rationalist while Bacon’s and Locke’s are empiricist, thus placing them at the heads of competing schools. But what is fundamental to all three is the central status of reason as objective and competent—in contrast to faith, mysticism, and intellectual authoritarianism of earlier ages. Once reason is given pride of place, the entire Enlightenment project follows.”

My response: One could argue that faith and mysticism can be metaphysically productive too, but there is little doubt that the Modern era, when reason was give pride of place, then the entire Enlightenment project followed, giving us the American system and way of life, and much of what is cherished about Western culture. If reasoning gave us some of the best times which humans have ever experienced, I cannot see with Peterson how intellect is the core of Luciferian dark pride in the world. Rather, emotion as unbridled passion, is the core of Luciferian pride in the world. That is the dismal legacy of irrationalism in most of human history.

Hicks-A23: “If one emphasizes that reason is a faculty of the individual, then individualism becomes a key theme in ethics. Locke’s A Letter Concerning Toleration (1689) and Two Treatises of Government (1690) are landmark texts in the modern history of individualism. Both link the human capacity for reason to ethical individualism and its social consequences: the prohibition of force against another’s independent judgment or action; limiting the power of government, and religious toleration.”

My response: Note the logical entailment necessitating the connectiveness of these four concepts: reason-individual-individualism-ethics versus passion-collective-collectivism-immorality. Hicks and Objectivists correctly concluded and link reasoning and thinking with being causal agents spurring the occurrence of the Age of Englightenment, a time when the individual came to be regarded as sovereign, that his personal power of reasoning was a potent faculty of innovation and inquiry, which he was allowed, even encouraged to indulge and exercise vigorously. With the rise of thinking individualists, what also arose was the advance of human civilization, when, for the first time, it came to be realized that the thinking individual, the average citizen, could serve as the ethical ideal for every citizen to emulate.

This world view of the Objectivists, favoring the rational individualist as an ethical exemplar who can be rightly proud of his merited achievement, almost violently contradicts Peterson’s example of the individual as an egotist, who, when and if he worships his own ego above worshiping the Divinity, he is a monster of Luciferian Pride, and Pride goeth before the Fall.

 

Hick-A23: “ . . . Individualism and science thus are the consequences of an epistemology of reason. Both applied systematically have enormous consequences.”

My response: It seems to me that the Objectivists’s objection to Peterson’s view on pride as from the Devil is the right response to Peterson.

Against Peterson, again I counter-suggest that humility in humans is what breed the presence both of the Devil, and Luciferian pride in the moral agent.